Anticipation is making me wait . . .

[From Bruce Abbott (970222.2205 EST)]

Bruce Gregory (970222.1650 EST) --

Well, it looks like "simulation" is in danger of becoming meaningless. I see
that listen to the Weather Channel is some form of simulation. Although
I can't identify exactly how it works. (Granted that forecasters at the NWS
_do_ use simulations.)

I have no idea what you mean by this. Simulation certainly has a specific
meaning the way _I_ understand the term. Are _you_ having a problem with it?

My interests are considerably more modest. I am not the least interested in
building control systems. I am interested in whether living control systems
incorporate mechanisms to simulate the environment in the sense that we can,
and must, model those simulations in order to understand how organisms
work. I have yet to see evidence that such an expansion of PCT is either needed
or desirable.

I believe that my example of fielding a ground-ball specifically involved a
living control system. My experience with this activity strongly suggests
to me that I am computing the ball's trajectory -- I can literally picture
the ball's path of anticipated travel through the air with each bounce --
and use this information to determine where I need to run in order to
intercept the ball. I take it for granted that humans (and animals) have
this ability and use it; therefore my interest is to _explain_ how it is
done. Your position, evidently, is that there is no evidence that it
occurs; thus, there is nothing to explain. If so, then I can only conclude
that your experience is vastly different from mine.

Bill Powers (970222.1510 MST) --

I think we often imagine that we do things at lower levels in one way, when
we actually do them quite differently. Bruce Abbott's example of "running to
the place where the ball is going to be" is an example. In tests of how
people actually run to catch balls, what is found is that the person runs so
as to maintain a constant rate of rise of the ball (or something related to
that). The result, of course, is that you're where the ball is when it comes
down, so you might be forgiven for assuming that this must be what you do --
run to where the ball is going to be. However, it might be more plausible to
assume that you start running and get the constant-rate-of-rise established
(which may not take more than a second or two), and then maintain the same
running direction and speed for a while before you look back again (like
Willie Mays). At least that would be consistent with the way ball-catchers
behave when they're looking all the time.

Yes, and it doesn't work worth doodly to explain how ball players are able
to run to the _approximate_ spot where a fly ball will land after taking
only a brief glance at the ball's trajectory and _then_ running like crazy
(without looking up back at the ball) toward that location. (This sort of
running occurs when the running speed must be maximized if there is to be
any hope of getting there on time. Also, my own experience is that I am
running toward a particular spot, not trying to maintain a particular
velocity and direction of run.) With respect to the ball's position the
fielder is in open loop mode, so miscalculations and disturbances like wind
gusts can create large errors that must be corrected (if time permits!) once
the player arrives at the spot and reacquires the visual image of the ball).
Yet without it, it would be impossible to catch the ball at all under these
circumstances.

Even just catching a thrown ball in one's mit requires a bit of estimation
-- at least for me. I tend to lose sight of the ball when it gets close if
it is traveling at any speed at all (the lenses in my eyes don't accommodate
rapidly enough to maintain focus), so I raise the mit to the position I
think the ball's trajectory will take it -- I'm certainly not watching the
ball all the way into the mit. For a brief moment I'm forced to operate in
open-loop mode, and yet I usually succeed in placing the mit in the ball's
path and trap the ball in the pocket. This is direct experience, so I'm
confident that I'm not mistaken about how I accomplish these things. For
this reason, assertions about there being no evidence that living organisms
do such computations carry the same weight with me as the assertion that
there is no such thing as vision.

I'm not claiming that depending on such estimates is a perfect substitute
for closed-loop control, but it's better than nothing when input from the CV
is interrupted and its short-term future path is reasonably predictable. I
was never good at actually _hitting_ the ball with a bat. My dad kept
admonishing me to "keep my eye on the ball," to no avail. I couldn't do it.
It was years before I realized that other people's eyes could actually keep
focused on the ball as it came in.

Bill Powers (970222.1450 MST) --

I guess I don't understand why it's necessary to decide what "anticipation"
means.

It's something all of us experience. In my book that's enough to justify
giving it a name. But why create a new, technical name when there is
already a perfectly good word in plain English to denote it? The question
then becomes, what to we mean by this term _here_, for the purpose of this
discussion? In my post I adopted a particular interpretation that equates
anticipation with model-based projection. I showed how even the simple
proportional-plus-rate controller can be viewed a involving such
extrapolation one dt ahead. This reveals a clear family connection between
this type of system and those using more elaborate projection algorithms.
Thus, exploring what we mean by "ancicipation" has, I think, provided some
insight into the relationship between ordinary control and control in
systems that incorporate some sort of "anticipatory" mechanism. This seems
justification enough for having undertaken the task.

Waiting in anticipation of your reply,

Bruce

[From Bruce Abbott (970223.0635 EST)]

Bruce Gregory (970223.0555 EST) --

Bruce Abbott (970222.2205 EST)]

Waiting in anticipation of your reply,

While you are waiting, I assume you are modeling it :wink:

No, of course not! Experience tells me that a reply will be forthcoming.
Having used this model to generate a prediction, I have no further need of
it. I simply wait in anticipation.

I presume that my reply to you comes as a total surprise! :->

Out of the Blue,

Bruce

[From Bruce Gregory (970223.0820 EST)]

Bruce Abbott (970223.0635 EST)]

No, of course not! Experience tells me that a reply will be forthcoming.
Having used this model to generate a prediction, I have no further need of
it. I simply wait in anticipation.

I presume that my reply to you comes as a total surprise! :->

Quite to the contrary. It is totally predictable on the basis of the
elaborate world-model I have been constructing. It is just one more
confirmation that I know _exactly_ what you are going to do and
say. (I am having some trouble controlling what you say, but I am
sure that is only a matter of time... :wink:

Bruce Gregory

[From Bruce Abbott (970223.0910 EST)]

Bruce Gregory (970223.0820 EST) --

Bruce Abbott (970223.0635 EST)

No, of course not! Experience tells me that a reply will be forthcoming.
Having used this model to generate a prediction, I have no further need of
it. I simply wait in anticipation.

I presume that my reply to you comes as a total surprise! :->

Quite to the contrary. It is totally predictable on the basis of the
elaborate world-model I have been constructing. It is just one more
confirmation that I know _exactly_ what you are going to do and
say. (I am having some trouble controlling what you say, but I am
sure that is only a matter of time... :wink:

This banter is good fun, but methinks you are dodging my argument. You do
indeed have an expectation as to how I am likely to respond, but it need not
be elaborate or precise to be of use. In many circumstances having _some_
idea of what to expect will usually permit better control to be exercised
than if things just seem to come out of nowhere and have to be dealt with
reactively, on the fly.

Expectantly,

Bruce

[From Bill Powers (970223.0725 MST)]

Bruce Abbott (970222.2205 EST)--

I believe that my example of fielding a ground-ball specifically involved
a living control system. My experience with this activity strongly
suggests to me that I am computing the ball's trajectory -- I can
literally picture the ball's path of anticipated travel through the air
with each bounce --
and use this information to determine where I need to run in order to
intercept the ball.

What you imagine that the ball is going to do is not information about what
the ball is going to do. It's an imagined projection of what the ball is
doing now, which is the only real information. This projection may or may
not be the basis on which you move to intercept the ball.

Consider the analogous situation of "predicting a collision" of your boat
with another boat. As you approach the other boat, you may be mentally
extrapolating your path and the other boat's path and imagining a collision,
but as any mariner will tell you, this is a very poor way to predict a
collision. You can easily imagine a collision when none is going to happen,
or worse, the opposite. The only sure way is to see whether the other boat
is maintaining (in present time) a constant bearing relative to your course.
If the bearing remains constant there is going to be a collision. To avoid
the collision, what you have to do is make sure that the bearing is
continuously changing. If, in fact, you frequently do predict and
successfully avoid collisions, it is probable that you do it through
observing the present-time bearing of the other boat, and NOT by
extrapolating the two paths, taking the two velocities and directions into
account -- even if you are completely convinced that you do it in the latter
way. There is nothing to prevent you from going through this extrapolation
in your mind as you approach the other boat, but it is probably not the
variable you're actually perceiving and controlling. Not if you most often
manage to avoid collisions.

I think that we often -- very often -- come up with conscious, cognitive
explanations of how we do things that reflect our beliefs more than what is
actually happening. The key to recognizing such situations is to ask whether
the critical parts of your explanation can actualy be observed. You say "I
can literally picture the ball's path of anticipated travel through the air
with each bounce -- and use this information to determine where I need to
run in order to intercept the ball." You may indeed imagine this picture,
but just ask yourself specifically HOW you use this information to determine
where you need to run to intercept the ball.

What you will find is a big blank. The actual computations would be
extremely complex, involving the forces acting on the ball and your body and
the laws of orbital mechanics. Doing them cognitively would be far too slow.
What you mean, I think, is that you MUST be doing these calculations, or
something in your brain must be doing them, because how else would you know
where the ball is going to go? In fact, I would guess that you experience no
calculations at all. They are purely hypothetical. So there is a critical
part of your interpretation of the experience that is not backed up by
observation. You're just describing what OUGHT to be going on, according to
your understanding of how people catch balls.

On the other hand, if you look for the constant-bearing phenomenon, you will
immediately see it going on, at least while you can see the ball. You will
do just as well in catching the ball -- and possibly a lot better -- if you
just forget about trying to imagine where the ball will come down, and
concentrate on keeping the critical perception in the right state throughout
the process. That will put you exactly where the ball is going to be at the
right time, without ever predicting either the place or the time.

I take it for granted that humans (and animals) have
this ability and use it; therefore my interest is to _explain_ how it is
done. Your position, evidently, is that there is no evidence that it
occurs; thus, there is nothing to explain. If so, then I can only
conclude that your experience is vastly different from mine.

No, not at all. I, too, can imagine that some kind of calculation is going
on, and I can even imagine a place and time where the ball is going to be at
the same place and time that I am there. But I doubt that the place I
imagine is the same place where I will catch the ball, or that I am capable
of imagining the exact time at which this will occur.

Obviously, this could all be worked out experimentally. Show a brief image
of a ball leaving a bat, stop the action and ask the observer to indicate
where the ball is going to come down, and when -- and then in what direction
the person should move, and how fast, to catch it. You could even do this
with real balls on a playing field (stretch a canopy over the field so you
have to run underneath it to the landing area). And you should test two
cases: in the first, the observer simply watches the initial part of the
ball's trajectory and then starts running, and in the second, the observer
can start running with the crack of the bat (to see how quickly the
constant-trajectory condition can be established before the trajectory
becomes invisible).

The problem with explanations is that they ALL seem right once you believe
in them. If you think that God guides you to the right place for catching
the ball, you can just FEEL the divine influence moving you magically to the
right place. Imagination will obediently provide any experience you tell it
to provide. This is why no explanation should be accepted just because you
can imagine it working. A skeptical approach is called for, especially with
regard to your own experiences. This is why I'm always looking for
demonstrations of explanations instead of just assuming that they're right
because they seem convincing.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bruce Gregory (970223.1230 EST)]

Bruce Abbott (970223.0910 EST)

You do
indeed have an expectation as to how I am likely to respond, but it need not
be elaborate or precise to be of use. In many circumstances having _some_
idea of what to expect will usually permit better control to be exercised
than if things just seem to come out of nowhere and have to be dealt with
reactively, on the fly.

Of course. But this is a long way from exercising control by comparing
the results of one's actions to a simulation of the world.

Bruce Gregory

[From Bruce Abbott (970223.1310 EST)]

Bill Powers (970223.0725 MST) --

What you imagine that the ball is going to do is not information about what
the ball is going to do. It's an imagined projection of what the ball is
doing now, which is the only real information. This projection may or may
not be the basis on which you move to intercept the ball.

Yes, of course: projections will be in error, to varying degrees. But it
would be a very strange thing indeed to have evolved a brain capable of
making those projections but incapable of using them, don't you think?

Consider the analogous situation of "predicting a collision" of your boat
with another boat. As you approach the other boat, you may be mentally
extrapolating your path and the other boat's path and imagining a collision,
but as any mariner will tell you, this is a very poor way to predict a
collision.

This boating example is one in which making good enough projections is
extremely difficult -- you are talking about ships observed at relatively
great distances, where their motion relative to your own heading appears
almost absent and it is extremely difficult to gage whether the other ship's
heading is at a right angle to yours or some other. By the time you are
close enough together to get a reasonably accurate projection, it is often
too late to take effective evasive action. So yes, this is a case where you
will have to take advantage of some other, less obvious relationship in
order to assure safety, as in your suggestion. However, this is no argument
that you won't use good projections when they are available.

I think that we often -- very often -- come up with conscious, cognitive
explanations of how we do things that reflect our beliefs more than what is
actually happening. The key to recognizing such situations is to ask whether
the critical parts of your explanation can actualy be observed. You say "I
can literally picture the ball's path of anticipated travel through the air
with each bounce -- and use this information to determine where I need to
run in order to intercept the ball." You may indeed imagine this picture,
but just ask yourself specifically HOW you use this information to determine
where you need to run to intercept the ball.

I agree that we need to consider -- and _test_ -- alternative explanations.
I am arguing _against_ accepting the notion that we _don't_ make such
projections _in the absence of such tests_.

What you will find is a big blank. The actual computations would be
extremely complex, involving the forces acting on the ball and your body and
the laws of orbital mechanics. Doing them cognitively would be far too slow.
What you mean, I think, is that you MUST be doing these calculations, or
something in your brain must be doing them, because how else would you know
where the ball is going to go? In fact, I would guess that you experience no
calculations at all. They are purely hypothetical. So there is a critical
part of your interpretation of the experience that is not backed up by
observation. You're just describing what OUGHT to be going on, according to
your understanding of how people catch balls.

By "computations" I don't mean taking sines and cosines of angles and all
that mathematical nonsense. This is an analog system, remember. And no, I
do not find a "big blank." What I find I'm doing is projecting the ball's
path along an imaginary curve -- continuing the arc. To the extent that I
am able to do this with reasonable accuracy, it is because I've seen the
path of such balls hundreds of times, and because my visual system contains
the algorithms for taking perspective into account (the basis of shape
constancy).

If I have the opportunity to continuously or at least frequently update my
perception of the ball's position relative to me, I will of course use that
perception, thus closing the loop and greatly improving my chances of
catching the ball. But we're not talking about that situation here.

On the other hand, if you look for the constant-bearing phenomenon, you will
immediately see it going on, at least while you can see the ball. You will
do just as well in catching the ball -- and possibly a lot better -- if you
just forget about trying to imagine where the ball will come down, and
concentrate on keeping the critical perception in the right state throughout
the process. That will put you exactly where the ball is going to be at the
right time, without ever predicting either the place or the time.

Right! I never suggested otherwise, when the ball remains visible to the
fielder.

I take it for granted that humans (and animals) have
this ability and use it; therefore my interest is to _explain_ how it is
done. Your position, evidently, is that there is no evidence that it
occurs; thus, there is nothing to explain. If so, then I can only
conclude that your experience is vastly different from mine.

No, not at all. I, too, can imagine that some kind of calculation is going
on, and I can even imagine a place and time where the ball is going to be at
the same place and time that I am there. But I doubt that the place I
imagine is the same place where I will catch the ball, or that I am capable
of imagining the exact time at which this will occur.

Actually, in the quoted paragraph I was talking to Bruce Gregory, not you,
but never mind. I also doubt that the place and time I imagine is the same
place and where/when I will catch the ball. If you will re-read my post you
will see that I allowed for significant error in those projections, stating
that the fielder generally will have to take corrective action as soon as he
turns and reaquires sight of the ball. My assertion was that by using my
projections I will be closer to the right place and time than would
otherwise be the case, not that I could catch the ball with my eyes closed.

Obviously, this could all be worked out experimentally. Show a brief image
of a ball leaving a bat, stop the action and ask the observer to indicate
where the ball is going to come down, and when -- and then in what direction
the person should move, and how fast, to catch it. You could even do this
with real balls on a playing field (stretch a canopy over the field so you
have to run underneath it to the landing area). And you should test two
cases: in the first, the observer simply watches the initial part of the
ball's trajectory and then starts running, and in the second, the observer
can start running with the crack of the bat (to see how quickly the
constant-trajectory condition can be established before the trajectory
becomes invisible).

Yes, and in fact I had in mind a computer simulation that might do the
trick. I am not in any way suggesting that these explanations should be
accepted without empirical proof. What I _did_ say was that I know for a
fact how _I_ personally experience this situation, and therefore am
unwilling to _reject_ this entirely reasonable (it seems to me) explanation
out of hand. Somehow I often do get to the approximate area where the ball
lands without keeping my eye on the ball during its entire flight. Somehow
I do hit a ball I can't see (at the moment I take my swing). Somehow I do
put up my mit and catch a ball that I last saw when it was still twenty feet
away. Those are the facts that need explaining.

I'm going outside in a few minutes and, seeing that it's snowing at the
moment, I plan to put on my winter coat. I anticipate that if I don't, I'm
going to freeze. If I were to respond only to the current state of my
temperature sensors, I'd just go out without the coat (as I am quite warm
now), get cold, and then take whatever action I could in order to
compensate. As this is definitely not what I generally do, I assume that
some more elaborate mechanism must be at work.

Rick is going to say that I'm controlling a logical variable (keeping
snowing AND wearing_coat true), (and this may be correct as far as it goes),
but it does not explain _why_ I would be interested in controlling this
variable _in the first place_. I would say that I'm using the visible
current state of one variable (snowing) to anticipate the state of another
(falling skin temperature) and taking action in advance of the anticipated
disturbance to the latter.

No doubt I'm the only person on CSGnet who formulates such plans -- the rest
of you just react to disturbances as they happen, right? (;->

Thinking ahead,

Bruce

[From Bruce Abbott (970223.1610 EST)]

Bruce Gregory (970223.1230 EST) --

Bruce Abbott (970223.0910 EST)

You do
indeed have an expectation as to how I am likely to respond, but it need not
be elaborate or precise to be of use. In many circumstances having _some_
idea of what to expect will usually permit better control to be exercised
than if things just seem to come out of nowhere and have to be dealt with
reactively, on the fly.

Of course. But this is a long way from exercising control by comparing
the results of one's actions to a simulation of the world.

Yes, I agree. What I've tried to illustrate is that useful projection (over
a limited time-span) can be achieved by extremely simple and limited models,
which may need to be consulted only once when needed (as in the example of
estimating about where the ball will be in order to choose a target position
to run toward). I've also tried to emphasize the inherent limitations of
such projections; they are certainly not to be preferred when continuous
input of the CV is available in a timely fashion. I'm certainly not
suggesting that elaborate world-simulations can replace real-time input over
the long run (except in _very_ special cases), nor am I suggesting that such
systems can deal adequately with unmodeled disturbances. My objective in
undertaking this analysis has been to better understand these systems and
their relationship to ordinary negative-feedback control systems, to
evaluate what advantage there may be to adding an "anticipatory" element to
the ordinary control structure, and to determine under what conditions such
an addition might improve control. In addition, I've suggested a few
examples in which such systems may play a role in the behavior of living
control systems.

What I've suggested is not incompatible with HPCT, as I understand it,
although I think that Bill P. prefers to focus at this stage of the game on
ordinary negative feedback control and introduce more complex organizations
such as those employing predictive elements only when it has been
demonstrated that an ordinary nonpredictive system cannot handle the data.
That's a good strategy so long as it doesn't result in overly strenuous
attempts to make the same shoe fit whether it belongs on that particular
foot or not.

Regards,

Bruce

[From Bill Powers (970224.0200 MST)]

Bruce Abbott (970223.1310 EST)--

Consider the analogous situation of "predicting a collision" of your boat
with another boat. As you approach the other boat, you may be mentally
extrapolating your path and the other boat's path and imagining a
collision, but as any mariner will tell you, this is a very poor way to
predict a collision.

This boating example is one in which making good enough projections is
extremely difficult -- you are talking about ships observed at relatively
great distances, where their motion relative to your own heading appears
almost absent and it is extremely difficult to gage whether the other
ship's heading is at a right angle to yours or some other. By the time
you are close enough together to get a reasonably accurate projection, it
is often too late to take effective evasive action. So yes, this is a
case where you will have to take advantage of some other, less obvious
relationship in order to assure safety, as in your suggestion. However,
this is no argument that you won't use good projections when they are
available.

Sorry, Bruce, but all this is hypothetical nonsense, which you would see
immediately if you went out and tested it. You've been brainwashed by years
of reading about "projections," so you've obligingly been imagining a sort
of perspective diagram of two objects approaching a collision point, one
labeled "me." But when you actually move yourself to approach something
else, the coordinate system moves with you; if you're actually going to
intercept it, what you see is an object at a constant bearing. Its distance
makes no difference. If it's six feet away from you, it will still be
approaching from a constant direction. You don't say "At 15:45:27.23 it is
going to be next to that pebble over there, and so am I, so it must be that
we will be at the same position at that time." You may _think_ this is what
you're doing, but that's only an intellectually-imagined interpretation
after the fact; what's really going on is quite different. You don't
intercept a moving object intellectually; you do it perceptually, using
perceptions you can actually see. You're just echoing the same intellectual
explanation that you've been fed. It ain't true.

If you and the approaching ship are on a collision course, the bearing will
be constant regardless of the angle between the courses. Your guess that the
angle has to be 90 degrees is wrong.

I agree that we need to consider -- and _test_ -- alternative
explanations. I am arguing _against_ accepting the notion that we _don't_
make such projections _in the absence of such tests_.

This "projection" explanation has been offered ever since I can remember,
without any testing. Why start testing now? One reason that the "baseball"
article in Science got so many people exercised was that they were
embarrassed because they'd always assumed something different, and didn't
want to admit that they'd got such a simple thing wrong, especially about
their own behavior. How can you observe your own behavior incorrectly? The
answer is, it's easy. People are no better at observing their own behavior
than they are at observing anyone else's behavior.

The people who catch on to PCT are those who are willing to put aside all
the explanations that others have taken for granted, and really LOOK at
what's going on, without a theoretical point of view blinding them. Then
they have the big AHA: of course I'm controlling my perceptions -- what else
is there to control? But some people take this insight as a personal
criticism and reject it: they're too used to imagining something else going
on, and they refuse to believe that they could have been wrong about
anything so simple and obvious. Since they don't want to believe that, they
don't believe it. And then they band together to reassure each other that
they COULDN'T have been wrong, and they write articles to each other about
how feedback is too slow, and feedforward is really great stuff and can
obviously do the job as they have alway known it could, and there's really
no need to revise what's in the textbooks they've written and the course
outlines they've devised (or adopted). All is well with the world, and only
nuts think that all of US could have got it all wrong for so long. Thank
goodness, I don't have to give back my PhD!

The constant-bearing hypothesis (or some constant-perception idea) is right
and the "projection" hypothesis is wrong, Bruce. Do you know what the
giveaway is? When you imagine projecting your own position to some future
position of the object you want to intercept, can you see yourself in the
picture? If the answer is yes, then you're imagining something you can't
perceive. When you actually do it, _you_ aren't in the picture.

By "computations" I don't mean taking sines and cosines of angles and all
that mathematical nonsense. This is an analog system, remember.

You don't perceive the analog computations, either.

And no, I
do not find a "big blank." What I find I'm doing is projecting the ball's
path along an imaginary curve -- continuing the arc.

That's just how you _fill in_ the big blank, with your imagination. You may
be consciously projecting the arc, but that's only to satisfy your belief
about what's happening; you could catch the ball without doing that, and
perhaps better because your attention would be on the perceptions you're
actually controlling instead of the ones you're imagining. You're continuing
the arc in objective space, but you're perceiving the ball from your own
moving point of view. If you're going to catch the ball, there isn't any
"arc" in your perceptions. The whole point is to eliminate it: when the ball
appears stationary, you'd better duck or get your mitt in front of the image.

Better give in, Bruce. The longer you go on describing these imagined
situations, the clearer you'll make it that you're not actually observing
what's happening.

To the extent that I
am able to do this with reasonable accuracy, it is because I've seen the
path of such balls hundreds of times, and because my visual system
contains the algorithms for taking perspective into account (the basis of
shape constancy).

If I have the opportunity to continuously or at least frequently update my
perception of the ball's position relative to me, I will of course use
that perception, thus closing the loop and greatly improving my chances of
catching the ball. But we're not talking about that situation here.

See what I mean? One imagined theoretical "fact" after another. You're only
describing what you _believe has to be happening_. You can't see any of
that. Go outside and have someone throw a ball while you maneuver to catch
it. You won't see the ball describing a neat parabolic arc. That's not how
the ball behaves in your actual perceptions. And it's your ACTUAL
PERCEPTIONS that you control (if you're catching a real ball or avoiding a
real collision), not the ones you imagine.

... in fact I had in mind a computer simulation that might do the
trick.

If you do this simulation by showing TWO dots on a stationary background
(one dot being "you"), you'll be doing it wrong. What you need is a
flight-simulator type of display, in which the display itself is your own
perceptual field. Consider how you land the airplane using Microsoft Flight
Simulator. Do you project your path through space so it will arrive just
above the start of the runway? Or do you just keep the image of the runway
stationary, a little below center, while it expands? Consider what you would
perceive on the screen if you were trying to collide with another airplane.
You would just see an image of the airplane some distance to one side of
center, getting bigger and bigger and _not moving_. If the other airplane
went behind a cloud, what would you do? Draw dotted lines in a mental
diagram? Or just maintain the same heading until you could see it again?

I am not in any way suggesting that these explanations should be
accepted without empirical proof. What I _did_ say was that I know for a
fact how _I_ personally experience this situation, and therefore am
unwilling to _reject_ this entirely reasonable (it seems to me)
explanation out of hand.

That's precisely the problem here. You have a fixed interpretation of what
you're experiencing, and you are unwilling (temporarily, I hope) to consider
that it may be wrong. You should be delighted if it proves to be wrong --
how often do we get a chance to learn something really new?

Somehow I often do get to the approximate area
where the ball lands without keeping my eye on the ball during its entire
flight. Somehow I do hit a ball I can't see (at the moment I take my
swing). Somehow I do put up my mit and catch a ball that I last saw when
it was still twenty feet away. Those are the facts that need explaining.

Fine, and I'm glad that you're now saying "somehow." There are several
explanations other than the one you're pushing. But until you stop defending
the current explanation, you won't be able to see the others.

I'm going outside in a few minutes and, seeing that it's snowing at the
moment, I plan to put on my winter coat.

Fine. Which arm did you imagine putting into its sleeve first? What you are
planning is to perceive that your coat is on you, so you've set a cognitive
reference level which, when you've accomplished it, can be described as "My
coat is on me." But just HOW you do that is left entirely to the lower-level
control systems, which will find the coat wherever you left it last, pick it
up and turn it so you can slip one arm in, feel around behind you for the
other sleeve, shrug it on, and zip it up. None of those details were in your
plan -- they couldn't be, because you can't predict the actual relationships
of your body to the coat until you encounter them. You can't plan that the
zipper will catch the lining and have to be freed. These "predictions" are
really just reference levels for some perceptual state of affairs that you
want to experience, and they're very sketchy in terms of actual lower-level
perceptions: just a vague snapshot here and there in the process, or even
just a verbal description ("Put arm A in sleeve B").

I anticipate that if I don't, I'm going to freeze.

No, that's just a verbal convention. You're not going to freeze, you're just
going to feel cold. But when you anticipate, you don't _experience_ the cold
unless you're hallucinating. In fact, in your way of putting it, I can hear
a little voice saying "Brucie, put on your coat or you're going to freeze."
Mothers always exaggerate.

If I were to respond only to the current state of my
temperature sensors, I'd just go out without the coat (as I am quite warm
now), get cold, and then take whatever action I could in order to
compensate. As this is definitely not what I generally do, I assume that
some more elaborate mechanism must be at work.

It's not more elaborate, it's simpler. It's a higher-level control process
that works with symbols standing for categories, from which all the
complexity has been stripped. If you're not freezing, you're warm. If you're
not warm, you're hot. This sort of planning is a higher-level process, and
it's not concerned with the details. The details get taken care of when you
encounter them. That's the beauty of the hierarchical concept. No one level,
considered by itself, is very complex -- or at least it's nowhere near as
complex as when you mix all the levels together into one big fuzzball.

Rick is going to say that I'm controlling a logical variable (keeping
snowing AND wearing_coat true), (and this may be correct as far as it
goes), but it does not explain _why_ I would be interested in controlling
this variable _in the first place_. I would say that I'm using the
visible current state of one variable (snowing) to anticipate the state of
another (falling skin temperature) and taking action in advance of the
anticipated disturbance to the latter.

Even to talk about this, you must categorize. "Snowing" is "snowing." At the
lower levels it could be slowing lightly or heavily or anywhere in between,
at any temperature from 0 to 40 F. But when the higher levels get hold of
these perceptions, all that's left is "snowing." We reason in categories,
which is why cognitive planning by itself is useless for actually directing
behavior. All a cognitive plan requires is that when the action takes place,
its consequence can be describe in terms of specific categories. That leaves
a lot of room for variation at the lower levels. When you "go outside,"
where do you find yourself? In your front yard? In Yankee Stadium? On the
Moon? Those places are all "outside."

So why did you formulate this plan? Not because when you go out in the snow
you get cold. That's just a fact. You formulate the plan because _you don't
want_ to "get cold," which is the way you categorize a whole variety of
experiences from a mild chill to a shivering flirtation with frostbite. If
you didn't have this intellectual level of control, you probably wouldn't
have the organization needed to plan ahead -- you just wouldn't go out, or
you'd go out and be cold, or you'd go out, encounter the cold, and scurry
back inside.

No doubt I'm the only person on CSGnet who formulates such plans -- the
rest of you just react to disturbances as they happen, right? (;->

Think hierarchically, Bruce, and all this will seem clearer.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bruce Abbott (970224.1620 EST)]

Bill Powers (970224.0200 MST) --

Bruce Abbott (970223.1310 EST)

Sorry, Bruce, but all this is hypothetical nonsense, which you would see
immediately if you went out and tested it. You've been brainwashed by years
of reading about "projections," so you've obligingly been imagining a sort
of perspective diagram of two objects approaching a collision point, one
labeled "me." But when you actually move yourself to approach something
else, the coordinate system moves with you; if you're actually going to
intercept it, what you see is an object at a constant bearing. Its distance
makes no difference. If it's six feet away from you, it will still be
approaching from a constant direction. You don't say "At 15:45:27.23 it is
going to be next to that pebble over there, and so am I, so it must be that
we will be at the same position at that time." You may _think_ this is what
you're doing, but that's only an intellectually-imagined interpretation
after the fact; what's really going on is quite different. You don't
intercept a moving object intellectually; you do it perceptually, using
perceptions you can actually see. You're just echoing the same intellectual
explanation that you've been fed. It ain't true.

Bill, this is a different case from the one we've been examining -- one in
which one gathers enough information to make a reasonable guess about where
some visually-acquired moving object will be in the near future and then
acts on that projection, without further input, until the final stage when
the image is reacquired. One can hardly keep the object at a constant
bearing under these conditions, and I was specifically talking about a
situation in which I was not in motion at the time the observation was made.

And no, I'm not "echoing" explanations I've been "fed." This is my own
interpretation, based on my own first-hand experience. If it's wrong, I
take full credit. (:->

If you and the approaching ship are on a collision course, the bearing will
be constant regardless of the angle between the courses. Your guess that the
angle has to be 90 degrees is wrong.

I _didn't_ guess that the angle has to be 90 degrees, so I can hardly have
been wrong about that. What I said (evidently not clearly enough) was that
the situation is one where the angle is difficult (if not impossible) to
judge. (The angle of regard is too close to the surface, given the distance
involved, to produce a reasonably accurate projection.) That means that
this example is one where the sort of projection I am talking about is
likely to fail -- badly. Therefore it is no surprise to me that one would
have to rely on other optical relationships that require repeated sampling
to detect (e.g., constant bearing).

This "projection" explanation has been offered ever since I can remember,
without any testing. Why start testing now? One reason that the "baseball"
article in Science got so many people exercised was that they were
embarrassed because they'd always assumed something different, and didn't
want to admit that they'd got such a simple thing wrong, especially about
their own behavior. How can you observe your own behavior incorrectly? The
answer is, it's easy. People are no better at observing their own behavior
than they are at observing anyone else's behavior.

Who was "exercised" by this explanation? I don't recall any great furor
arising from this article . . . And note that the article dealt with a
slightly different situation -- the fielder was able to repeatedly glance up
and make adjustments to his path of travel. Because this involves repeated
sampling, there can be essentially closed-loop control throughout. I have
absolutely no problem with the proposed explanation for this performance,
under this condition. Now, how does he intercept a grounder? Different method?

The people who catch on to PCT are those who are willing to put aside all
the explanations that others have taken for granted, and really LOOK at
what's going on, without a theoretical point of view blinding them. Then
they have the big AHA: of course I'm controlling my perceptions -- what else
is there to control? But some people take this insight as a personal
criticism and reject it: they're too used to imagining something else going
on, and they refuse to believe that they could have been wrong about
anything so simple and obvious.

I would hope that after all the interactions _we've_ had that you wouldn't
put me into that latter group. I'm willing to entertain alternative
explanations if they make sense to me, especially those that do no violence
to the basic principles of PCT. In my view it is _you_ who is unwilling to
consider alternatives, not me.

The constant-bearing hypothesis (or some constant-perception idea) is right
and the "projection" hypothesis is wrong, Bruce.

I'm sure it is -- under circumstances where it can work. I'm asking about
what you do when it can't.

Do you know what the
giveaway is? When you imagine projecting your own position to some future
position of the object you want to intercept, can you see yourself in the
picture? If the answer is yes, then you're imagining something you can't
perceive. When you actually do it, _you_ aren't in the picture.

What I perceive is the point I estimate I will have to reach if I am to have
any hope of catching the ball, and some idea of the amount of time available
in which to get there. These become references for where I will run and how
fast.

By "computations" I don't mean taking sines and cosines of angles and all
that mathematical nonsense. This is an analog system, remember.

You don't perceive the analog computations, either.

Oh, for goodness sake. The perceptual machinery does the analog
"computations." _I_ just perceive their result.

That's just how you _fill in_ the big blank, with your imagination. You may
be consciously projecting the arc, but that's only to satisfy your belief
about what's happening; you could catch the ball without doing that, and
perhaps better because your attention would be on the perceptions you're
actually controlling instead of the ones you're imagining. You're continuing
the arc in objective space, but you're perceiving the ball from your own
moving point of view. If you're going to catch the ball, there isn't any
"arc" in your perceptions. The whole point is to eliminate it: when the ball
appears stationary, you'd better duck or get your mitt in front of the image.

You keep going back to this non-applicable example. I have already granted
that if I have the ball in view, I may very well use this type of perceptual
control, but the example I proposed is one in which this strategy is
impossible. Therefore we must either deny that I am able to arrive at some
location anywhere near the ball's path under my scenerio, or develop an
alternative explanation for my ability to do so.

What's so difficult about accepting the idea that under some conditions we
can and do rely on estimates or forecasts to improve our ability to control?
Even the running ball-player who can only occasionally glance back at the
ball must run for a time without the continuous input that would allow him
to keep the ball on a constant visual bearing, and then correct any error
that has built up between sightings.

An expert pool player can visualize where each ball will go after being
struck, including any effect of putting "english" on the cueball. The only
direct control possible is of the motion imparted to the cue -- after that
the whole scene goes ballistic, i.e., open loop. From one perspective the
player is only controlling the perception of the cue stick's position and
motion, but where did the references for those CVs come from? My guess is
that they come from the player's ability to project the paths of each ball
while mentally varying the cue stick's tip-position and angle relative to
the cueball, and the pattern of force and motion imparted to the stick.
This requires a sophisticated intuitive model of the physics involved, one
that requires considerable experience to develop. The task is made somewhat
simpler, however, by the relatively consistent characteristics of the table,
cue stick, and balls.

Similarly, a golfer must learn how to control her swing in order to get the
ball going in the right direction for the right distance, but there is much
more to golf than that. One must learn to take into account such factors as
the effect of any apparent wind, and (when putting) the topography of the
ground over which the ball must travel, the type of grass, and so on. These
must be taken into account when planning what club to use and how to strike
the ball. The better golfer not only has more precise control over her
swing, but a better ability to take these factors into account when planning
what to do.

I am not in any way suggesting that these explanations should be
accepted without empirical proof. What I _did_ say was that I know for a
fact how _I_ personally experience this situation, and therefore am
unwilling to _reject_ this entirely reasonable (it seems to me)
explanation out of hand.

That's precisely the problem here. You have a fixed interpretation of what
you're experiencing, and you are unwilling (temporarily, I hope) to consider
that it may be wrong. You should be delighted if it proves to be wrong --
how often do we get a chance to learn something really new?

You misunderstand my meaning. I mean that my interpretation is based on
experience and seems reasonable to me. I do not mean that I therefore
accept that explanation sans evidence. It is a working hypothesis, and I
would be delighted with the result no matter which explanation -- mine,
yours, or someone else's -- proved to be correct. What I reject is
precisely what you reject: unwillingness to consider alternatives.

Fine, and I'm glad that you're now saying "somehow." There are several
explanations other than the one you're pushing. But until you stop defending
the current explanation, you won't be able to see the others.

To the extent that I defend this hypothesis, it is to argue that it is an
hypothesis worth testing -- that it cannot be rejected out of hand based on
some logical flaw or conflict with fact. It seems to me that premature
rejection is what the other side of this debate is trying to promote. And
Bill, I am both aware of and willing to consider alternatives.

This is getting longish and I have to run, so I'll be brief with respect to
the bit about puting on a coat because one infers cold from snow, knows that
one will get chilly running about outdoors without a coat, and takes advance
action to avoid getting chilly. First, I am clear on how a hierarchical
organization simplifies planning: each level must deal only with those
things of direct concern to it, allowing the lower levels to take care of
the details that concern _them_. When I decide to put on my coat, I do not
have to simultaneously concern myself with how I will do it. That is not
the issue.

The issue is, why do I put on my coat, if I am not currently chilly?
Certainly I am not acting in response to current perceptions of bodily
comfort. The reference to have a coat on must have come from higher up, but
where? Somewhere in my system there is an awareness of the relationship
between seeing that it is snowing outside and the likely temperature of the
outside air (i.e., cold). Somewhere there is an awareness of the likely
effect of cold air on the perception of bodily comfort, in the absence of
wearing a coat, and of how wearing a coat is likely to modify this
relationship. In fact, I am able to verbalize these expected relationships.
I know that I don't like to be cold, and take action to prevent it. I can
neatly formalize my decision as logic-level control of the logical variable
cold_outside AND wear_coat; making this true entails setting a reference for
puting on my coat. But I don't think that this description captures why I
put on my coat. I certainly have no self-perception that I am trying to
make some logical state true, even if the result is _as if_ that is what I do.

I can think of alternatives that would still be consistent with a hierarchy
of control, but alas, I'm expected for an early dinner and have to end here.

Alternatively,

Bruce

[From Bill Powers (970224.1935 MST)]

Bruce Abbott (970224.1620 EST)--

Bill, this is a different case from the one we've been examining -- one in
which one gathers enough information to make a reasonable guess about
where some visually-acquired moving object will be in the near future and
then acts on that projection, without further input, until the final stage
when the image is reacquired. One can hardly keep the object at a
constant bearing under these conditions, and I was specifically talking
about a situation in which I was not in motion at the time the observation
was made.

Good, you didn't lose your temper at me, but I'll bet you were tempted.

What I'm trying to get you to see is that the customary way of explaining
these phenomena makes assumptions for which there is no evidence. And this
includes what we think, to ourselves, about how we do these things. A lot of
what we think is based on imagination, not observation.

And no, I'm not "echoing" explanations I've been "fed." This is my own
interpretation, based on my own first-hand experience. If it's wrong, I
take full credit. (:->

Do you mean that nobody in your psychology courses or papers you read
offered the same explanation? It seems strange that I've heard this
explanation so many times, while you, a professional psychologist, never
encountered it before you took up baseball.

If you and the approaching ship are on a collision course, the bearing
will be constant regardless of the angle between the courses. Your guess
that the angle has to be 90 degrees is wrong.

I _didn't_ guess that the angle has to be 90 degrees, so I can hardly have
been wrong about that. What I said (evidently not clearly enough) was
that the situation is one where the angle is difficult (if not impossible)
to judge. (The angle of regard is too close to the surface, given the
distance involved, to produce a reasonably accurate projection.)

I see that I misunderstood you. You're saying that when your point of view
is sufficiently above the surface, you can extend the two courses, yours and
that of the other object, to see where they intersect. Then, I presume you
mark off distance intervals along these two paths in proportion to the
velocities of yourself and the other object, and if the number of intervals
is not the same at the point of intersection, you adjust your speed and/or
course until this is the case. Having done this, you no longer need to
observe the other object, because you know how fast and in what direction to
travel.

Is this more or less what you experience when you turn your back on the ball
and start running at a calibrated speed? If not, how DO you make these
estimates? What makes you sure that these estimates are even being made?

That means that
this example is one where the sort of projection I am talking about is
likely to fail -- badly. Therefore it is no surprise to me that one would
have to rely on other optical relationships that require repeated sampling
to detect (e.g., constant bearing).

The constant-bearing approach does not require continuous sampling, except
at the beginning. Once you have established a speed and direction of
movement, and for any reason you can't observe any more, what is the most
effective thing to do? Keep traveling the same way at the same speed. I
hinted at this in speaking of trying to collide with another airplane in
Flight Simulator. This method accomplishes exactly what the "projection"
method accomplishes, and requires the same initial observations, but does it
without actually making any projections.

Who was "exercised" by this explanation? I don't recall any great furor
arising from this article . . .

After the article about the experiment using video cameras (something like
20 years after the initial article on catching a baseball) there were a
number of letters proposing other methods, mostly of the type you suggest,
and strong rejection of the article's interpretations. I know I saw these
commentaries, but can't remember where.

And note that the article dealt with a
slightly different situation -- the fielder was able to repeatedly glance
up and make adjustments to his path of travel. Because this involves
repeated sampling, there can be essentially closed-loop control
throughout. I have absolutely no problem with the proposed explanation for
this performance, under this condition.

Good. Now, starting with that method, what is the least change necessary to
account for a similar performance when the ball is not in sight at all
during the middle portion of its trajectory? Is it necessary to go all the
way to "calculating the landing point?" I've already indicated how I think
it's done.

Now, how does he intercept a grounder? Different method?

Same method, with modifications. Generally, infielders are taught to "get
their bodies behind the ball," which in perceptual terms means moving
yourself (if possible) until the ball is not moving either left or right.
When it's not moving left or right, it's coming right at you (same as
landing an airplane in a crosswind). Of course it's still going to hit a
bump and jump over or under your glove. If you can't get your body behind
the ball, you try to get your glove on a collision course with the ball.

The constant-bearing hypothesis (or some constant-perception idea) is
right and the "projection" hypothesis is wrong, Bruce.

I'm sure it is -- under circumstances where it can work. I'm asking about
what you do when it can't.

You ask what other _real present-time_ perceptions can be controlled that
will give almost as good a result. You assume that anything involving very
complex calculations will fail miserably, and will be used only as a last
resort, without much hope of success.

Do you know what the
giveaway is? When you imagine projecting your own position to some future
position of the object you want to intercept, can you see yourself in the
picture? If the answer is yes, then you're imagining something you can't
perceive. When you actually do it, _you_ aren't in the picture.

What I perceive is the point I estimate I will have to reach if I am to
have any hope of catching the ball, and some idea of the amount of time
available in which to get there. These become references for where I will
run and how fast.

How do you perceive that point? By what method do you carry out this
estimation? How do you perceive an "amount of time?"

If, as you say, you can make these estimates while standing still, you ought
to be able to specify the landing location immediately. So a test ought to
be fairly simple. Lay out a numbered string grid in the possible landing
area, and have someone throw balls, with you specifying the grid location of
landing immediately after the ball is thrown (or batted, of course). Then
record the guess and the actual landing position.

Actually, if you pause after the ball is hit to make these estimates, before
you start running, you are never going to make it to the majors. A typical
major-league second baseman, going after a blooper to center, turns
immediately and starts running, twisting back to watch the ball as he gets
up to speed, and then turns and runs for a while at the same speed before
turning around to adjust position for the final part of the trajectory. When
a deep drive starts off, a center-fielder playing in close may well start
running while watching the ball, and then just turn and go hell for leather
to the wall, because he's unable to go fast enough to establish the right
perceptual condition (constant trajectory, constant slow rise, whatever) and
just runs as fast as he can hoping to catch a carom off the wall, or make a
showboat leap.

I don't know how this second-baseman or center-fielder would describe how he
catches a ball. He might say "I just run to where it's going to come down."
That may well be how it seems -- but if he catches the ball often enough to
earn his bloated salary, that's not likely to be how he actually does it.
Being good at something doesn't mean you understand how you really do it.
It's easy to understand this when you hear a batting instructor explaining
to an interviewer that batted balls have more "carry" when the air is humid
(I've heard commentators say the same thing about golf balls, so gee, maybe
impetus theory really does work).

By "computations" I don't mean taking sines and cosines of angles and
all that mathematical nonsense. This is an analog system, remember.
You don't perceive the analog computations, either.

Oh, for goodness sake. The perceptual machinery does the analog
"computations." _I_ just perceive their result.

Don't you "Oh for goodness sake" ME, pal. You perceive what you perceive.
You're GUESSING that it's the result of a computation. You think it is
reasonable that it be the outcome of a computation. But you don't know WHAT
computation, and you don't know what the computation is based on. It might
be based on perceptual variables which you aren't attending to consciously,
and the computation might be completely different from the one you imagine.

You keep going back to this non-applicable example. I have already
granted that if I have the ball in view, I may very well use this type of
perceptual control, but the example I proposed is one in which this
strategy is impossible. Therefore we must either deny that I am able to
arrive at some location anywhere near the ball's path under my scenerio,
or develop an alternative explanation for my ability to do so.

This is getting repetitious, but I'm glad you tacked on that final clause. I
think it is relatively easy to find an alternative explanation that doesn't
call for unnamed and unsensed calculations of very complex nature that go on
where you can't see them. Maybe such calculations do go on, but before I
would be driven to refer to them, I would exhaust all the simpler
explanations based on control of perceptions that are clearly available and
don't need to be imagined.

What's so difficult about accepting the idea that under some conditions we
can and do rely on estimates or forecasts to improve our ability to >control?

It's not difficult unless you're trying to account for skilled behavior. It
doesn't take much skill to predict that the sun is going to rise tomorrow,
and plan accordingly, or to look at thunderheads out your window and reach
for an umbrella. This is the sort of simple stuff we can do with cognitive
planning, because it's elementary. But as soon as the forecasts become at
all complex, we have to rely on slow artificial methods; adding up the
checkbook to see if we have any money left, programming a computer to
predict what tomorrow's weather will be; solving equations with pen and
paper to see the best number of newspapers to stock at the newsstand. If you
have to estimate anything involving a quadratic or cubic equation, you can
count on being off by a large amount - unless you actually do the algebra.

Even the running ball-player who can only occasionally glance back at the
ball must run for a time without the continuous input that would allow him
to keep the ball on a constant visual bearing, and then correct any error
that has built up between sightings.

An expert pool player can visualize where each ball will go after being
struck, including any effect of putting "english" on the cueball. The
only direct control possible is of the motion imparted to the cue -- after
that the whole scene goes ballistic, i.e., open loop. From one
perspective the player is only controlling the perception of the cue
stick's position and motion, but where did the references for those CVs
come from? My guess is that they come from the player's ability to
project the paths of each ball while mentally varying the cue stick's
tip-position and angle relative to the cueball, and the pattern of force
and motion imparted to the stick. This requires a sophisticated intuitive
model of the physics involved, one that requires considerable experience
to develop. The task is made somewhat simpler, however, by the relatively
consistent characteristics of the table, cue stick, and balls.

Right, no "twisted cue, and a cloth untrue, and elliptical billiard balls."

Part of my misspent high-school youth was misspent while managing a
community-house rec-room with a real billiard table. I learned the fine art
of three-cushion billiards from an underemployed house painter named,
honestly, Rembrandt Noble. I didn't get good enough to beat Rem, but he
taught me enough that nobody else would play with me. He taught me all those
things you mention, about stick speed, spin, and angles. Rem was obviously
not a physicist; emphatically not a physicist. He was an empiricist. He
taught me how to chalk a cuetip around the edges but not the center, to
control spin. He taught me how to hold the cue and stroke it so you could
feel the living echoes of the impact running up and down the cue, the sign
of a perfect contact. He taught me how to pick my spot on the cueball to
impart spins of varying degrees (about three degrees is all, but three
standardized spins is all you need). He taught me how to use the diamonds on
the rails to estimate the bounce angles, and showed me how contact with the
rail could impart spin, and how an initial spin would affect the angle of
reflection off the rail. He showed me how a ball behaves in the corner with
and without spin, close to the corner and farther and farther from it, for
shallow and steep approaches. He showed me how to pick angles in corners
that were forgiving of errors. He showed me how to stroke a curve ball.

All this was obviously planning and forecasting of the highest order. And it
was all completely cognitive. It boiled down to learning what perceptions to
control at what reference levels in order to create, most of the time, a
desire result. It was about what to imagine, too, but mostly it was about
what to see and feel. Of quantitative estimation there was very little; that
was mostly about learning the angles at which balls would bounce apart when
contacting with the line of centers at various angles.

This is why I don't utterly reject the idea of SOME kind of model-based
control. But it's also why I associated it almost totally with the higher
levels of perception, and with reasoning and conscious imagination.

The same thing goes for golf, as you mention, and other sports like bowling
and baseball. The whole trick, in all these sports, is learning what
perceptions to control and in what reference conditions. The reason is that
this is ALL you can control while "in the act." The less estimating and
predicting you have to do, the better you will be at the sport. You have to
learn to remember what you did and what happened, so you can SLOWLY vary
what you do, time after time, to control the average state of the result.
But above all, you have to see through all the false explanations and
theories and misdirections to the variables that can be controlled directly,
simply, and easily.

I rather pounded on you in my post; got carried away (I visited Rick only a
week ago). I was reacting to what, to me, sounded like a traditional banal
explanation that everyone knows is true and nobody has really tested.
Obviously, we do project and predict and forecast and even simulate things.
But I contend that we do this mainly when accuracy doesn't matter or when
lower-order systems will take care of the details. Planning, I contend, is
greatly overrated; that's probably why large organizations spend so much
money on it. It's vulnerable to inaccurate or plain wrong assumptions, and
unexpected contingencies, and inability to carry out exactly the prescribed
actions. And it usually produces about the result you would expect from
knowing those deficiencies. In spite of this, there are people who just love
planning, and are willing to excuse just about any failure by blaming it on
something other than the plan -- which is, of course, at the same time a
legitimate excuse and the basic reason that plans don't work. Something
other than the planned future is always happening. Everything would have
worked perfectly if my secretary hadn't got sick on that particular day.

So you see, you're the victim of a pet peeve.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bruce Abbott (970225.0905 EST)]

Bill Powers (970224.1935 MST) --

Good, you didn't lose your temper at me, but I'll bet you were tempted.

No, but I _was_ starting to have visions of two or three burly men working
you over with brass knuckles until you said, "O.K., O.K.! We _do_
anticipate!" (;->

What I'm trying to get you to see is that the customary way of explaining
these phenomena makes assumptions for which there is no evidence. And this
includes what we think, to ourselves, about how we do these things. A lot of
what we think is based on imagination, not observation.

Understood and accepted.

And no, I'm not "echoing" explanations I've been "fed." This is my own
interpretation, based on my own first-hand experience. If it's wrong, I
take full credit. (:->

Do you mean that nobody in your psychology courses or papers you read
offered the same explanation? It seems strange that I've heard this
explanation so many times, while you, a professional psychologist, never
encountered it before you took up baseball.

It's not a question that ever came up in any courses I took, and I haven't
done any research in this area. I played baseball _long_ before I ever
heard of psychology.

I see that I misunderstood you. You're saying that when your point of view
is sufficiently above the surface, you can extend the two courses, yours and
that of the other object, to see where they intersect. Then, I presume you
mark off distance intervals along these two paths in proportion to the
velocities of yourself and the other object, and if the number of intervals
is not the same at the point of intersection, you adjust your speed and/or
course until this is the case. Having done this, you no longer need to
observe the other object, because you know how fast and in what direction to
travel.

That would be the general idea, but I don't think it's that systematic
(marking off intervals etc.) It's more like perception -- "seeing" the
object moving along a course at some speed, like playing back a remembered
motion. And it's not very accurate.

Is this more or less what you experience when you turn your back on the ball
and start running at a calibrated speed? If not, how DO you make these
estimates? What makes you sure that these estimates are even being made?

I don't know how I do it. I don't know how I perceive the motion of a ball
I'm looking directly at, either. Yet in the latter case I know that there
must be some mechanism generating that perception, and I suspect that the
same mechanism can be used in imagination mode to project the ball's path,
with limited accuracy, because I seem to be aware of such projections.

What I perceive is the point I estimate I will have to reach if I am to
have any hope of catching the ball, and some idea of the amount of time
available in which to get there. These become references for where I will
run and how fast.

How do you perceive that point? By what method do you carry out this
estimation? How do you perceive an "amount of time?"

How do you perceive rate of motion? Doesn't that require perception of time
as well as distance? I certainly don't think anything like "I've got about
ten seconds"; it's more a feeling of relative urgency -- whether I need to
run like crazy or can take my time.

If, as you say, you can make these estimates while standing still, you ought
to be able to specify the landing location immediately. So a test ought to
be fairly simple. Lay out a numbered string grid in the possible landing
area, and have someone throw balls, with you specifying the grid location of
landing immediately after the ball is thrown (or batted, of course). Then
record the guess and the actual landing position.

Yes, it's a testable hypothesis, as I've been saying. And quite possibly wrong.

Actually, if you pause after the ball is hit to make these estimates, before
you start running, you are never going to make it to the majors.

Well, that explains why I became a college professor instead . . . In fact
I never was very good at baseball -- probably relied too heavily on
inefficient cognitive strategies.

Oh, for goodness sake. The perceptual machinery does the analog
"computations." _I_ just perceive their result.

Don't you "Oh for goodness sake" ME, pal.

This was a phrase frequently spoken by Suzie Wong in the movie of the same
name (although she did not use it in the book!). From her lips it was quite
endearing, fo goodness sake! (She couldn't pronounce the "r.") But I guess
I'm no Suzie Wong.

What's so difficult about accepting the idea that under some conditions we
can and do rely on estimates or forecasts to improve our ability to >control?

It's not difficult unless you're trying to account for skilled behavior. It
doesn't take much skill to predict that the sun is going to rise tomorrow,
and plan accordingly, or to look at thunderheads out your window and reach
for an umbrella. This is the sort of simple stuff we can do with cognitive
planning, because it's elementary. But as soon as the forecasts become at
all complex, we have to rely on slow artificial methods;

Yes, I agree that we aren't terribly good at the complex stuff, which is why
artificial methods (and computers, analog or digital) were invented.

The task is made somewhat simpler, however, by the relatively

consistent characteristics of the table, cue stick, and balls.

Right, no "twisted cue, and a cloth untrue, and elliptical billiard balls."

These defects complicate the task, but it's not as if the table, balls, and
cue were of varying and unknown composition and shape, with unpredictable
hardness, resiliancy, frictional characteristics, and so on. Standard
construction removes most of the variance, making it possible to detect
useful regularities on which good habits can be built.

He taught me how to hold the cue and stroke it so you could
feel the living echoes of the impact running up and down the cue, the sign
of a perfect contact.

"Feel the living echoes of the impact running up and down the cue" . . . I
_love it_! That's poetry, Bill. How do you do it?

All this was obviously planning and forecasting of the highest order. And it
was all completely cognitive. It boiled down to learning what perceptions to
control at what reference levels in order to create, most of the time, a
desire result. It was about what to imagine, too, but mostly it was about
what to see and feel. Of quantitative estimation there was very little; that
was mostly about learning the angles at which balls would bounce apart when
contacting with the line of centers at various angles.

This is why I don't utterly reject the idea of SOME kind of model-based
control. But it's also why I associated it almost totally with the higher
levels of perception, and with reasoning and conscious imagination.

Well, that's a relief! As often turns out to be the case, we really aren't
so far apart as it may have seemed at first.

I rather pounded on you in my post; got carried away (I visited Rick only a
week ago).

Oh, no. You mean you can catch it from _contact_? (;->

Obviously, we do project and predict and forecast and even simulate things.
But I contend that we do this mainly when accuracy doesn't matter or when
lower-order systems will take care of the details.

If you look back on my posts on this topic, you will see that this is what
I've been saying -- and I'm talking about _both_ sentences, not just the first.

So you see, you're the victim of a pet peeve.

Well, next time you take it out for a walk, try to make sure it doesn't bite
anyone. (;->

Today we had our first clear morning since mid-January, and I finally got to
see Hale-Bopp. With a full moon in the west, the seeing conditions weren't
ideal, but I had no trouble spotting the comet in the east north-east, it's
tail pointing straight up. To think it's come all this way just to put on
its little show for us; it would be such a shame to miss it.

Regards,

Bruce

[From Bill Powers (970225.1020 MST)]

Bruce Abbott (970225.0905 EST)]

Looks like we're back into agreement again, or good enough for the nonce.

As to my remark about visiting Rick, I take the 5th.

Best,

Bill P.