FW: Social Reality

From[Bill Williams 29 May 2004 8:30 PM CST]

Bruce,

Bill Powers says in his recent post that,

There is not as much space between us as there sometimes seems to be.

I don't know about you Bruce, but I don't believe a word of this.

Bill Powers goes on to say that,

I think the main difference is that I have followed the logic of perception
to its final conclusion

What Bill Powers doesn't seem to realize is that _logic_ is perhaps one of the best examples of an agreement of the sort you are talking.

When Powers resorts to inserting logic into his argument, he is conceeding that more is involved than merely our perceptions. As, he says, he has followed "the logic." Now control theory adds a bit of refinement to our understanding of what it means to have "followed the logic." Following didn't mean giving up being an autonomous control system. However, when we arrive here we obviously don't invent the world into which we arrive. That world doesn't and can't dictate what an autnomous control system will do. But, the world into which we arrive has features that are coordinated. How is this coordination achived, by control systems. Does the coordination extend beyond the specimen's of the population taken as organicly distinct control systems. Well, of course. Is this coordination purposeful? Of course it is.

Bill claims that by pointing out that people come actually do come to an agreement you are exhibiting a failure to understand control theory.

He says,

you're still resisting,

[understanding PC by ]

wanting to preserve at least your own area of expertise as dealing with > facts, not perceptions and interpretations.

Well, of course "facts" are a kind of perception and interpretation. But, not all perceptions are equally valuable. Some perceptions are organized so that they are more reliable than other perceptions. Science is both a matter of reference levels and habits of perception. Some perceptions are more organized by habits or norms than other perceptions. By making such an accusation, Bill Powers is exhibiting an aspect of solipcism. He hasn't been interested enough to find out what you actually think, and instead presents this charge that doesn't have anything to do with what you think.

Powers goes on to say that,

I don't preserve any area of expertise as exempt from the
judgement that it's a perception, my perception.

When Powers says that it is a perception, and that it is his perception, he is leaving out the consideration that his perception would have been much different had he been a member of a different culture. Not you understand that the culture would have "influenced" him in the sense of causing him to do things in a different way, but rather because being in the culture he was, at the time and place that he was, he made choices in an environment that had been purposefully organized. In a culture without a vacumn tube it is likely that Bill Powers would not have written _B:CP_.

Now Powers tell you that,

When you're willing to do that, too, [when you realize that it is all perception] you and he will,

be speaking the same language.

I don't think we ought to worry about speaking PCT. We can use control theory to our advantage without having to become "individualist" in the old fashioned sense. A human civilization creates an enviornment ( All of the agency as we understand it is expressed by the population of specimens each of them acting autonomously. ) that is to some extent coordinated inorder to achieve various purposes. Neither econmics nor linguistics makes any sense in the absence of an assumption that behavior is purposeful. Neither economics nor linguistic theory requires any mythic causal super-organic powers. But, neither makes any sense without the conception of a cultural heritage that evolves through time as the result of the purposeful behavior of a population in an environment. In economics every transaction includes an agreement. In linguistics, I assume that the language itself, like logic, and mathematics, represents a measure of agreement. Without violating any principle of control!
  theory, there should be no difficulty, in principle in elaborating upon the meaning of an agreement in control theory terms. And, I think, despite Powers' rejection of your argument, I think you and Martin Taylor have made a good start.

From my standpoint, I don't perceive that we have had an argument with Powers. From what I understand of what he has said, he certainly isn't arguing with me. And, when I read what he says about you, I have difficulty believing that you would be of the opinion that, in the main or altogether, he is arguing with you. I don't expect to convince Bill Powers of this. So, what is the point?

It has been a long time since I thought there was any point to arguments about what is really real and how could we know it. But, that is what Bill Powers seems to think methodological arguments are about. Basically Powers holds methodological and philosophic inquiry in contempt. The result is all too evident. If you wish to go on arguing with Bill when he isn't doesn't seem to be paying attention to your, or my position for that matter either, I think that I will choose to enjoy the argument as a spectator. Unless something productive emerges-- which is unlikely.

Bill Williams

···

-----Original Message-----
From: Williams, William D.
Sent: Sat 5/29/2004 9:26 PM
To: CSGnet
Subject: Re: Social Reality

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)]

Bill Williams 29 May 2004 8:30 PM CST--

Bill Powers goes on to say that,

> I think the main difference is that I have followed the logic of perception
> to its final conclusion

What Bill Powers doesn't seem to realize is that _logic_ is perhaps one of
the best examples of an agreement of the sort you are talking.

Is that so? I think that logic, or rule-following, or reasoning (all
approximations to a particular kind of brain activity) is a basic function
of the brain, without which you couldn't do many of the things you do.
There are many examples of the way people use this facility, which do show
that there are social agreements of this kind. However, they are all
employing the same mental equipment, and identifying just what that
equipment is is more interesting (from the standpoint of a theory of the
brain) than arguing about any one example.

When Powers resorts to inserting logic into his argument, he is conceeding
that more is involved than merely our perceptions. As, he says, he has
followed "the logic." Now control theory adds a bit of refinement to our
understanding of what it means to have "followed the logic."

Logic is a particular kind of perception in HPCT. The "logic of perception"
to which I alluded is simply that whatever one is aware of, it has to be a
perception rather than a direct contact with the world (that's a
principle). This follows from the best and simplest of our knowledge -- our
observations, analyses, and agreements -- about how sensory endings and
nerves work. None of that information was available to any thinker before,
at the earliest, 1820 or so, and wasn't fully understood until the 20th
Century. This means that Kant, Hume, and other intellectual heros long dead
were not playing with a full deck, or at least a deck as full as ours is
now. I have read most of the philosophers you refer to, but have not been
inclined to make as many allowances for quaint beliefs and ignorance as you
do, and therefore don't read good sense into what has often struck me as
nonsense. Ideas don't become true just because one asserts them in a
bullying, persistent, persuasive, or clever manner.

Following didn't mean giving up being an autonomous control system.
However, when we arrive here we obviously don't invent the world into
which we arrive.

That's "obvious", is it? That's such a persuasive argument that I guess I
should believe you. Actually, I think that a great deal of invention is
involved, so the world a child experiences requires far more inventive
effort to bring into being than is assumed by the "tabula rasa" theorists.
The child can't help imposing his human nature onto the sensory impressions
received from the world, which, I have proposed, is why that world takes
the shapes it does: intensities through system concepts. Of course the
_particular_ intensities through system concepts that the child acaquires
by way of perceptions are influenced by the details of the world that
exists and that others have helped to shape, but those are so highly
variable across and within persons that we know they can't be innate.

That world doesn't and can't dictate what an autnomous control system
will do. But, the world into which we arrive has features that are
coordinated. How is this coordination achived, by control systems. Does
the coordination extend beyond the specimen's of the population taken as
organicly distinct control systems. Well, of course. Is this coordination
purposeful? Of course it is.

"Of course", is it? There you go again with those devastatingly effective
arguments. But somehow just throwing the word "coordination" in, without
definition or explanation, doesn't satisfy my desire to understand the way
it might have at one time. What coordinations? What coordinator?
Coordination, in my dictionary. carries a sense of someone who sees
multiple activities going on, and is able to direct them so that they are
coordinated -- all working in concert at the same level, order, or rank.

Bill claims that by pointing out that people come actually do come to an
agreement you are exhibiting a failure to understand control theory.

He says,

> you're still resisting,

[understanding PC by ]

> wanting to preserve at least your own area of expertise as dealing
with > facts, not perceptions and interpretations.

You were the one who inserted [understanding PC by]. Talk about invention!
My meaning was very specific but you managed to turn it into something
else. I meant that Bruce (like you, but not so radically) is resisting the
idea that _all_ of experience is perception, rather than just most of it.
This is a precursor to PCT, not an idea that depends on understanding PCT.
You can't really cite Kant or Hume or any of those guys; you can cite only
your faulty memory of what you read, your partial recall of what they said,
your private interpretation of what they meant, your 20th century
interpretation of words set down centuries ago -- in short, your perception
of your own memories and thoughts. If you think you have found some point
of view from which, at last, you can simply report the True Facts of
Philosophy As They Are, you have not taken the last steps to grasping the
real problem we face. In fact you've given up the effort.

Well, of course "facts" are a kind of perception and interpretation. But,
not all perceptions are equally valuable. Some perceptions are organized
so that they are more reliable than other perceptions. Science is both a
matter of reference levels and habits of perception. Some perceptions are
more organized by habits or norms than other perceptions. By making such
an accusation, Bill Powers is exhibiting an aspect of solipcism. He
hasn't been interested enough to find out what you actually think, and
instead presents this charge that doesn't have anything to do with what
you think.

Your grasp of True Reality is, as usual, breathtaking, but I am learning to
lean into the wind and hold my ground. I am far less a solipsist than you
are, because I realize not only that there is, most probably, a Real
Reality, but I realize how little I know about it. You, on the other hand,
seem to have it all figured out, without even a theory -- just some old
familiar words like habit and norm whose meanings (what few they have) long
predate theories like PCT. A reality that is that easy to understand just
has to be made up.

Powers goes on to say that,

> I don't preserve any area of expertise as exempt from the
> judgement that it's a perception, my perception.

When Powers says that it is a perception, and that it is his perception,
he is leaving out the consideration that his perception would have been
much different had he been a member of a different culture.

The contents of my perceptions no doubt would be different. The types of
perception I have I do doubt would be different.In Los Angeles, last
summer, I asked Zhang Hua Xia, a Chinese philosopher who has translated and
is publishing B:CP in China this year, if my proposed levels of perception
made any sense in the Chinese culture. He said very emphatically yes, they
were very close to Chinese thought. I have asked others, Europeans and
Russians, the same question and have got the same answers. My list may not
be exhaustive and it may not be quite right, but it seems to describe
aspects of brain operation that are human, not cultural.

  Not you understand that the culture would have "influenced" him in the
sense of causing him to do things in a different way, but rather because
being in the culture he was, at the time and place that he was, he made
choices in an environment that had been purposefully organized. In a
culture without a vacumn tube it is likely that Bill Powers would not
have written _B:CP_.

I agree. There were other essential ingredients, too. Learning how to
analyze and design signal-handling circuits of several kinds. Studying
neuroanatomy. Learning about the mathematics of negative feedback loops.
Building and interacting with negative feedback loops (which involved
interacting with nature but not people). Learning alternate theories of
behavior and being dissafisfied with them. Reading various philosophers,
being impressed at first, then acquiring doubts. Watching how people
behave, in the wild and in organized experiments. All these experiences and
more went into B:CP and PCT.

So?

I don't think we ought to worry about speaking PCT. We can use control
theory to our advantage without having to become "individualist" in the
old fashioned sense.

I think it would be best to go back to the idea of "individual" in the old
fashioned sense. I know that this is a red-flag or knee-jerk word for you,
but it is highly descriptive of the human situation, and you should get
over your prejudice even if people you admired taught it to you (I'm sure
you wouldn't claim you invented it). People are individuals; their physical
boundary is their skin. It's very easy to distinguish them from their
environments, if you try sincerely.

Saying that people interact and learn from each other doesn't make them
less individual, any more than saying you can build things with Lego blocks
takes away the individual identity of the blocks. And most particularly,
saying that people can form groups doesn't magically give any of them the
ability to know more about the world than they can get from sensory
receptors. It doesn't give us, who are talking about these things, that
ability, either. What they know about the groups they are in depends
strictly on the perceptual systems they apply to their inputs; if they
misunderstand, they will build their social life on that misunderstanding,
not on the "reality."

A human civilization creates an enviornment ( All of the agency as we
understand it is expressed by the population of specimens each of them
acting autonomously. ) that is to some extent coordinated inorder to
achieve various purposes.

If somebody perceives in terms of coordination, and decides to act as a
coordinator, and finds an effective way to coordinate, and carries it out
successfully -- yes. Then we see the effects of that person's purposes. If
people develop "social perceptions" having to do with cooperation (meaning,
working together without supervision), we will see (if we, too, develop
similar perceptions) that coordination is being purposively controlled. Why
do we need to go beyond that, and reify the "society" or "culture" as if it
is something automonous itself? Why give purposiveness to the collective,
which is not even a control system?

Neither econmics nor linguistics makes any sense in the absence of an
assumption that behavior is purposeful. Neither economics nor linguistic
theory requires any mythic causal super-organic powers. But, neither
makes any sense without the conception of a cultural heritage that evolves
through time as the result of the purposeful behavior of a population in
an environment.

But you contradict yourself in successive sentences. We do not need any
mythic super-organic powers or beings. Period. Therefore we do not need to
reify something called a "cultural heritage", an evolving purposive being
separate from the individuals in the culture, having power over them. We
can explain the interactions among individuals by putting models of
individuals together in an environment and observing how they interact. We
can observe and predict the changes (some changes) that take place over
time. And we can see that everything that the culture is and does is a
product of what the individuals are and do.

It has been a long time since I thought there was any point to arguments
about what is really real and how could we know it.

Ah, an agreement at last. But I doubt that it will hold up. I no longer
worry about how much I experience of reality because the answer is "none of
it." You seem to agree that _some_ of it is simply our own perceptions, but
you reserve certain aspects of experience, such as your own reasoning or
the written works of other people, as being exempt from this generalization.

Basically Powers holds methodological and philosophic inquiry in contempt.
The result is all too evident. If you wish to go on arguing with Bill when
he isn't doesn't seem to be paying attention to your, or my position for
that matter either, I think that I will choose to enjoy the argument as a
spectator. Unless something productive emerges-- which is unlikely.

I'd say your contempt for Bill Powers exceeds mine for the philosophers. I
admire your unlimited self-confidence, even if it is misplaced.
Unfortunately, all that it means is that you are impervious to
disagreements; all you have to do is point out that any disagreement is
"obviously" wrong, for reasons that are "all too evident," or "absurd," or
results from ignorance or a character defect, and you have settled the
matter. Of all the philosophical arguments I have been unimpressed by, that
approach probably impresses me the least. I think that one Pope is more
than sufficient, and I don't even agree that that one can ever speak
infallibly.

Bill P.

[Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.1416]

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)]

Bill Williams 29 May 2004 8:30 PM CST--

.... Bruce (like you, but not so radically) is resisting the
idea that _all_ of experience is perception, rather than just most of it.

I'm sorry, but re-reading Bruce Nevin (05.28.2004 22:50 EDT) (Full
version), I don't get that impression. Neither do I get it from Bill
Williams.

I think Bill P. is resisting the idea that perceptual constructs can
come into being by way of interaction between one individual and a
community of other individuals who tend to react similarly to the
actions of that one individual. In other words, Bill P. is resiting
the idea that the reality of a cultural artifact is as precise as is
the reality of a stone that is available for the Bishop to kick.

Both the rock and the cultural artifact have a reality attested by
the reliability of perceptual changes related to actions upon the
artifact. Inconsistent changes of the perception tend to discredit
the perceptual reality of the entity: if I kick the rock now and hurt
my toe, it's probably real, but if I don't hurt my toe because my
foot continues unhindered the next time I demonstrate, was the rock
real, or was it an illusion supported by someone's interposition of a
real steel beam when I last kicked?

If I act linguistically so as to greet you in a normal way when I
first see you, and you return the greeting in a normal way, day after
day, is not the cultural artifact of a greeting convention real? If
my greeting is answered sometimes by a kick, sometimes by a "Hello",
and sometimes by a "Get lost", is not the reality of that cultural
artifact (in the culture of you and me) somewhat dubious? If I
observe that for most dyads, the "normal" greeting is followed by a
"normal" response, and that if I am a member of such a dyad, I can
arrange to perceive the "normal" response most of the time by issuing
a "normal" greeting at the "normal" moment, am I not justified in
perceiving the reality of the cultural artificat as being similar to
that of the rock (and considerably more "real" than that of an atom)?

The fact that we can perceive as "real" cultural constructs that have
evolved through aeons of interpersonal interaction does not mean that
we resist the idea that all experience is perception.

Martin

[Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.1416]

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)]

Bill Williams 29 May 2004 8:30 PM CST--

.... Bruce (like you, but not so radically) is resisting the
idea that _all_ of experience is perception, rather than just most of it.

I'm sorry, but re-reading Bruce Nevin (05.28.2004 22:50 EDT) (Full
version), I don't get that impression. Neither do I get it from Bill
Williams.

I think Bill P. is resisting the idea that perceptual constructs can
come into being by way of interaction between one individual and a
community of other individuals who tend to react similarly to the
actions of that one individual. In other words, Bill P. is resiting
the idea that the reality of a cultural artifact is as precise as is
the reality of a stone that is available for the Bishop to kick.

Both the rock and the cultural artifact have a reality attested by
the reliability of perceptual changes related to actions upon the
artifact. Inconsistent changes of the perception tend to discredit
the perceptual reality of the entity: if I kick the rock now and hurt
my toe, it's probably real, but if I don't hurt my toe because my
foot continues unhindered the next time I demonstrate, was the rock
real, or was it an illusion supported by someone's interposition of a
real steel beam when I last kicked?

If I act linguistically so as to greet you in a normal way when I
first see you, and you return the greeting in a normal way, day after
day, is not the cultural artifact of a greeting convention real? If
my greeting is answered sometimes by a kick, sometimes by a "Hello",
and sometimes by a "Get lost", is not the reality of that cultural
artifact (in the culture of you and me) somewhat dubious? If I
observe that for most dyads, the "normal" greeting is followed by a
"normal" response, and that if I am a member of such a dyad, I can
arrange to perceive the "normal" response most of the time by issuing
a "normal" greeting at the "normal" moment, am I not justified in
perceiving the reality of the cultural artificat as being similar to
that of the rock (and considerably more "real" than that of an atom)?

The fact that we can perceive as "real" cultural constructs that have
evolved through aeons of interpersonal interaction does not mean that
we resist the idea that all experience is perception.

Martin

···

-----Original Message-----
From: Control Systems Group Network (CSGnet) on behalf of Martin Taylor
Sent: Mon 5/31/2004 1:29 PM
To: CSGNET@listserv.uiuc.edu
Subject: Re: FW: Social Reality

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1315)]

Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)--

If somebody perceives in terms of coordination, and decides to act as a
coordinator, and finds an effective way to coordinate, and carries it
out
successfully -- yes. Then we see the effects of that person's
purposes. If
people develop "social perceptions" having to do with cooperation
(meaning,
working together without supervision), we will see (if we, too, develop
similar perceptions) that coordination is being purposively
controlled. Why
do we need to go beyond that, and reify the "society" or "culture" as
if it
is something automonous itself? Why give purposiveness to the
collective,
which is not even a control system?

...

We do not need any
mythic super-organic powers or beings. Period. Therefore we do not
need to
reify something called a "cultural heritage", an evolving purposive
being
separate from the individuals in the culture, having power over them.
We
can explain the interactions among individuals by putting models of
individuals together in an environment and observing how they
interact. We
can observe and predict the changes (some changes) that take place over
time. And we can see that everything that the culture is and does is a
product of what the individuals are and do.

I think these two little paragraphs provide a nice, quick summary of
the PCT view of society and culture, a view that is derived from (and
can be understood only in the context of) modeling. Society and culture
are perceptions (of aspects of the behavior of collections of
individuals) that exist in the brains of individual controllers.
Society and culture are not autonomous, purposive agents (control
systems). They are a perceived product of what individuals are and do.

Best regards

Rick

···

---
Richard S. Marken
marken@mindreadings.com
Home 310 474-0313
Cell 310 729-1400

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.1316 MDT)]

Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.1416 --

I think Bill P. is resisting the idea that perceptual constructs can
come into being by way of interaction between one individual and a
community of other individuals who tend to react similarly to the
actions of that one individual. In other words, Bill P. is resiting
the idea that the reality of a cultural artifact is as precise as is
the reality of a stone that is available for the Bishop to kick.

I'm resisting all right, but not what you think I'm resisting.

I give cultural artifacts exactly the same degree of reality as stones.
They are both perceptions. Johnson thought he was refuting Berkeley by
kicking the stone, but that was because he did not consider the stone or
the kicking or the pain in the toe or the observed trajectory of the stone
to be perceptions. If he kicked a real stone and his toe really hurt and
the stone really flew through the air, how could those things be "merely"
perceptions? He simply did not apply the principle to its limit.

Let's not confuse "perception" with "illusion." Perceptions are real. What
is unknown is their connection to anything that is not a perception.
According to the best models of sensory perception available, that means we
do not know directly the connection of perceptions to anything outside the
nervous system. That does not, of course, prevent us from constructing
models of what lies outside the nervous system.

Both the rock and the cultural artifact have a reality attested by
the reliability of perceptual changes related to actions upon the
artifact. Inconsistent changes of the perception tend to discredit
the perceptual reality of the entity: if I kick the rock now and hurt
my toe, it's probably real, but if I don't hurt my toe because my
foot continues unhindered the next time I demonstrate, was the rock
real, or was it an illusion supported by someone's interposition of a
real steel beam when I last kicked?

You're still talking only about perceptions and their relationships to each
other expected from prior experience.If you kicked the rock and felt
nothing you would be extremely surprised because that would be contrary to
prior experience with perceptions of kicking and perceptions of rocks. But
that has nothing to do with the question, "If I see myself kicking, am I
"really" moving a leg -shaped object throughg "space" in relation to a
"rock"-shaped object?" How could you ever answer that question? You would
have to be able to know about your own kicking action (and the stone)
without using any perceptual system: not vision, kinesthesia, hearing, or
any other system. And there is no other way. Take away the perceptual
systems and you have nothing.
So there is no way to compare perceptions with whatever reality we believe
is giving rise to them.

The same goes for "cultural artifact." Given your perception of one of
those, how would you go about proving that there is an entity outside your
nervous system corresponding to it? There is no way. If you could find a
way, you would probably win some sort of important prize, because no one
before you has done it.

If I act linguistically so as to greet you in a normal way when I
first see you, and you return the greeting in a normal way, day after
day, is not the cultural artifact of a greeting convention real?

Just as real as the greeting and the return of greeting, which is to say
that you are describing your perceptions. We perceive regularities in the
relationships among perceptions, and come to rely on them. The question is
not whether regularities exist, or at least whether the observer honestly
believes that they exist on the basis of whatever perceptual evidence is
available. It is whether there is some regularity in reality, outside the
nervous system, that corresponds to, or at least is remotely related to,
the perceived regularity.

This makes A GREAT DEAL OF DIFFERENCE when you start to ask why such
regularities are perceived. If you simply assume that any regularity
corresponds to a real regularity outside the brain, then you can forget
about postulating perceptual input functions that (like frequency
filters).impose regularity on variable phenomena. If a number of events
lead to the same behavior, you can forget about looking for perceptual
variables they all disturb, and concentrate on finding what is similar
across these "stimuli." When you exempt perceptual phenomena from being
perceptual phenomena, and say instead that they are "real", your whole
explanatory focus changes; you look for external rather than internal causes.

I'm not saying we should never look for external causes. When we find a
model that points strongly toward an external cause, that is an exciting
moment, for we are quite possibly in touch with a genuine fact about the
World Outside. But before we can allow ourselves that conclusion, we have
to exhaust the possibilities of internal causes, because they are far more
prevalent. Every would-be scientist learns this; you have to eliminate all
biases, all illusions, all desires, all habitual preferences, all selection
effects, all hasty preconceptions -- and that is a hard and never-ending
battle. Maybe impossible, but we get as close as we can. Most of the time,
winning this battle comex down to admitting that once again, we are talking
about a human perception and nothing else that we know about.

If my greeting is answered sometimes by a kick, sometimes by a "Hello",
and sometimes by a "Get lost", is not the reality of that cultural
artifact (in the culture of you and me) somewhat dubious?

Martin, all this is about the "reality" of relationships among perceptions,
isn't it? You're asking whether it would be reasonable for you to perceive
regularities among perceptions when you perceive regularity, and to
perceive none when you perceive none. Of course it would be reasonable. But
if you want to ask whether the regularity you perceive corresponds to some
regularity in the real universe -- whether there "really is" a regularity
-- you're asking an unanswerable question. To answer it, we would have to
compare your perception of regularity with the actual regularity of the
extra-perceptual universe -- and of course we can't do that. We have only
one element of the comparison, your perception. We have nothing to compare
it to.

If I observe that for most dyads, the "normal" greeting is followed by a
"normal" response, and that if I am a member of such a dyad, I can
arrange to perceive the "normal" response most of the time by issuing
a "normal" greeting at the "normal" moment, am I not justified in
perceiving the reality of the cultural artificat as being similar to
that of the rock (and considerably more "real" than that of an atom)?

The fact that we can perceive as "real" cultural constructs that have
evolved through aeons of interpersonal interaction does not mean that
we resist the idea that all experience is perception.

Put that way, I can't object. What we percieve "as real" is not reality,
but a perception to which we assign the label, "real" (the "aeons", I would
claim, are not perceptions, but imaginations). That doesn't change it from
being a perception in our heads to being direct knowledge of Real Reality.
Nothing can do that.

We don't spend a lot of time worrying about what is a perception and what
is not. There are perceptions that we prefer to think of as realities,
because we rely on them routinely and have to take them for granted to get
on with life. But when we're trying to form a theory of human nature, we
have to be more careful, because what we assume is real determines what we
think still needs an explanation. If you think that social customs are
real, in the sense of NOT being someone's perceptions of social customs but
actually existing outside the actor, then you don't need to explain how it
is that a person can perceive them, or what role his perceptions play in
determining the idea of society he maintains and controls. You simply look
for the effects that social customs have on the actor, and you assume that
all actors in the society are affected by the same customs. This is very
different from assuming that people control in the light of _what they
perceive_ to be actual social customs outside themselves, and therefore
exploring the effects of changing perceptions, and differences in the
behavior of actors relative to the group in which they live.

When I speak of carrying the idea of "it's all perception" to its limit, I
mean what we're talking about here: not exempting any object of observation
from the statement. When we can do that, we have arrived at a starting
point. From this starting point we can begin to build models that include
as much of experience as possible, both models of the brain (itself a
model), and once in a while, models of a reality independent of the brain.
It was only by doing this that I could even conceive of the 11 levels of
perception. Before I got the idea that the world is what we perceive, I
thought that items belonging to every one of these levels were simply part
of a real universe independent of me. I was a budding physicist, a naive
realist. Just look around you. If you think all of that is anything but a
set of perceptions, then you will have to accept that items at every level
from intensities to system concepts really exist in a world outside you,
and the only thing required for understanding is that your brain learn to
recognize what is already there. That's what the "coding" theory of
perception is all about.

I used to believe that way. I don't any more.

Best,

Bill P.

[Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.1641]

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1315)]

Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)--

If somebody perceives in terms of coordination, and decides to act as a
coordinator, and finds an effective way to coordinate, and carries it
out
successfully -- yes. Then we see the effects of that person's
purposes. If
people develop "social perceptions" having to do with cooperation
(meaning,
working together without supervision), we will see (if we, too, develop
similar perceptions) that coordination is being purposively
controlled. Why
do we need to go beyond that, and reify the "society" or "culture" as
if it
is something automonous itself? Why give purposiveness to the
collective,
which is not even a control system?

...

We do not need any
mythic super-organic powers or beings. Period. Therefore we do not
need to
reify something called a "cultural heritage", an evolving purposive
being
separate from the individuals in the culture, having power over them.
We
can explain the interactions among individuals by putting models of
individuals together in an environment and observing how they
interact. We
can observe and predict the changes (some changes) that take place over
time. And we can see that everything that the culture is and does is a
product of what the individuals are and do.

I think these two little paragraphs provide a nice, quick summary of
the PCT view of society and culture, a view that is derived from (and
can be understood only in the context of) modeling. Society and culture
are perceptions (of aspects of the behavior of collections of
individuals) that exist in the brains of individual controllers.
Society and culture are not autonomous, purposive agents (control
systems). They are a perceived product of what individuals are and do.

Whereas _I_ think that although not wrong, both Bill P's and Rick's
remarks are too simplistic. Not only are they simplistic, they are
dangerous, in that they imply that the study of culture is not
appropriate within PCT. Unless one understands cultural interactions
within a PCT theoretical culture, one is unlikely to be able to
develop an understanding of how to mitigate the problems that occur
when cultural differences lead to conflict.

Bill says: "Why give purposiveness to the collective, which is not
even a control system?" This is a straw man set-up. Maybe I have
failed to read something, but I don't remember anyone attributing
purposiveness to "society" or "culture."

What has been asserted is that perceptions of entities in one's
environment are controlled by acting upon them in ways appropriate to
the entities and to the perceptions in question. If there's a rock
nearby, and one wants to see from a higher vantage point, one can
stand on the rock. If there's a person nearby and one wants help, one
can use langauge to ask. But only if the person belongs to an
appropriate linguistic (and probably social) culture will they give
the desired help. Likewise, if the rock is actually made of paper,
standing on it won't provide you a higher vantage point.

Societies and cultures, and languages and dialects, are as real (and
as purposive) as rocks. They just happen to be constructed out of the
interactions of people (or fish, or monkeys, or birds), rather than
out of the interactions of inanimate materials. To control one's
perceptions when interacting with other people, one must have learned
(consciously or through life-long reorganization) what acts have what
probable influences on what perceptions, exactly as one must have
learned how to act on the inanimate world in order to influence one's
perceptions.

So I will continue to reify my perception of my "desk" and
"computer", as well as of my "cultural heritage".

Martin

From [Marc Abrams (2004.05.31.1655)]

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.1316 MDT)]

Let's not confuse "perception" with "illusion." Perceptions
are real.

There is _no_ difference to an individual.

From the old TV commercial; "Is it Memorex or is it on tape?"

Your insistence on not thinking of imagination as 'real' perceptions is
a folly.

As much 'experience' takes place in our heads as takes place in the
so-called 'environment'.

Marc

Considering how often throughout history even intelligent people have
been proved to be wrong, it is amazing that there are still people who
are convinced that the only reason anyone could possibly say something
different from what they believe is stupidity or dishonesty.

Being smart is what keeps some people from being intelligent.

Thomas Sowell

Don't argue with an idiot; people watching may not be able to tell the
difference.

Anon

I don't approve of political jokes. I've seen too many of them get
elected

Anon

From[Bill Williams 31 May 2004 3:50 PM CST]

Rick Marken's Post contributes nothing to a productive discussion of the issues. If he said what he says below would be dishonest if he understood with any accuracy both sides of the discussion.

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1315)]

Bill Powers (2004.05.31.0629 MDT)--

If somebody perceives in terms of coordination, and decides to act as a
coordinator, and finds an effective way to coordinate, and carries it
out
successfully -- yes. Then we see the effects of that person's
purposes. If
people develop "social perceptions" having to do with cooperation
(meaning,
working together without supervision), we will see (if we, too, develop
similar perceptions) that coordination is being purposively
controlled. Why
do we need to go beyond that, and reify the "society" or "culture" as
if it
is something automonous itself? Why give purposiveness to the
collective,
which is not even a control system?

## Bill Powers warns us not become confused by the difference between an
## illusion and the "reality" that he calls perception.

···

##
## What Bill is

...

We do not need any
mythic super-organic powers or beings. Period. Therefore we do not
need to
reify something called a "cultural heritage", an evolving purposive
being
separate from the individuals in the culture, having power over them.
We
can explain the interactions among individuals by putting models of
individuals together in an environment and observing how they
interact. We
can observe and predict the changes (some changes) that take place over
time. And we can see that everything that the culture is and does is a
product of what the individuals are and do.

I think these two little paragraphs provide a nice, quick summary of
the PCT view of society and culture, a view that is derived from (and
can be understood only in the context of) modeling.

## This is a false isssue dragged in by the guy who's effort to model an ## ecnomy was descrbed by Bill Powers as "a giant leap in the wrong direction.

Society and culture
are perceptions (of aspects of the behavior of collections of
individuals) that exist in the brains of individual controllers.

## There is nothing in human experience that corresponds to Rick's notion of
## "individual controllers."

Society and culture are not autonomous, purposive agents (control
systems).

## No one here is claiming that society and culture are autonomous, purpusive
## control systems. For Rick, and Bill Powers too for that matter to bring
## this in is, as Marter point out mistaken.

They are a perceived product of what individuals are and do.

## Again, There is nothing in human experience that corresponds to Rick's
## notion of "individual controllers." There never has been.

Bill Powers in a previous post admitted the point that, I and I think Bruce Nevin, and Martin Taylor are making. Bill Powers, however, doesn't go on the draw the obvious, though perhaps subtle point, that in social analysis the specimen enters into an ongoing world. The specimen matures in a context of a civlization that consists in part of, and is controlled by, on-going agreements. Nothing in this statement has anything at all to say about a reified conception of culture. It is a point of view that makes good sense from a control theory standpoint.

Bill and Rick, however rather than argue with the "real" difficulty that is involved here are directing their arguments to this specious charge concerning "reified culture."

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1430)]

Martin Taylor (2004.05.31.1416) --

I think Bill P. is resisting the idea that perceptual constructs can
come into being by way of interaction between one individual and a
community of other individuals who tend to react similarly to the
actions of that one individual.

I think Bill P. (like myself) is mainly resisting the idea that society
and culture are real autonomous agents. But I guess we're also
resisting the idea that perceptions _are_ reality.

Both the rock and the cultural artifact have a reality attested by
the reliability of perceptual changes related to actions upon the
artifact.

Both the rock and the cultural artifact are _functions_ of reality, but
they are not the reality themselves. The model of reality that we use
in PCT says that there is really no such thing as a rock, for example.
What is really "out there" is a collection of elementary particles
organized into atoms and molecules that we perceive as rocks, water,
people and so on. What you perceive as a rock can also be seen as a
way marker, a paper weight, a fossil, a weapon, etc. All those things
are "really" there to the same extent that the rock is there. They are
perceptual representations of what is _really_ out there -- a
collection of atoms and molecules.

If I act linguistically so as to greet you in a normal way when I
first see you, and you return the greeting in a normal way, day after
day, is not the cultural artifact of a greeting convention real?

Yes. In the same sense the rock is real. It is a real perception that
exists only for a system that can perceive this interaction as a
greeting. But, as in the case of the rock, this particular "reality"
(the greeting) can exist as many different perceptual realities; as a
scene in a play, part of a complex plot to rob a bank, or a couple of
control systems each controlling its own perception of a sequence. We
can use modeling to determine that the latter comes closest to what is
really going on.

Regards

Rick

···

---
Richard S. Marken
marken@mindreadings.com
Home 310 474-0313
Cell 310 729-1400

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1450)]

Martin Taylor (2004.05.31.1641) --

Whereas _I_ think that although not wrong, both Bill P's and Rick's
remarks are too simplistic. Not only are they simplistic, they are
dangerous, in that they imply that the study of culture is not
appropriate within PCT.

There is no such implication in Bill or my remarks. What I would like
to see is the study of culture from a PCT perspective. A big part of
that perspective is _modeling_. What I would like to see is culture and
society studied using models rather than an endless streams of words.

Societies and cultures, and languages and dialects, are as real (and
as purposive) as rocks.

See my previous post. They are really perceptions. But they are
certainly not really out there, in the world on the other side of our
senses. PCT accepts the models of physics and chemistry as the best
current representation of what is really out there. There are no
societies, cultures, languages or dialects in the physics or chemistry
models of reality.

Regards

Rick

···

---
Richard S. Marken
marken@mindreadings.com
Home 310 474-0313
Cell 310 729-1400

[Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.17.16]

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.1316 MDT)]

Bill, I don't think we have much disagreement about fundamentals.
Especially I have no disagreement with the basic premise that our
perceptions are all we know of reality. It is on that basis that I
argue for the equivalent reality of rocks and of cultural artifacts.

When we go further than simply saying that, and start talking about
theories like PCT, which assume we work in some "real reality" that
behaves in a way independent of, but influenced by, us, then we get
into areas that warrant discussion.

If you simply assume that any regularity
corresponds to a real regularity outside the brain, then you can forget
about postulating perceptual input functions that (like frequency
filters).impose regularity on variable phenomena.

Why deliberately do that?

If a number of events
lead to the same behavior, you can forget about looking for perceptual
variables they all disturb, and concentrate on finding what is similar
across these "stimuli."

Why forget?

When you exempt perceptual phenomena from being
perceptual phenomena, and say instead that they are "real", your whole
explanatory focus changes; you look for external rather than internal causes.

Why so?

In fact, I would argue quite the contrary to all these statements.

Martin, all this is about the "reality" of relationships among perceptions,
isn't it?

Yes and no. Yes, in the absolute sense that perceptions are all I
have to work with. No in the sense that some of those perceptions are
actually of my intended outputs, and the regularities are the effects
of those outputs on the world. It's rather like the difference
between an observational science like astronomy, where the observer
can't manipulate the stars, and a laboratory science liek chemistry,
where the experimenter can change the constituents of his mixtures
without hindrance from the outer world (other than that the stores
clerk says there isn't any of what the chenist wants).

There's an assumption that teh relationship between an intended
action and a change in perception is more than coincidental -- that
something "out there" allows the link to occur, and it isn't simply a
mischievous scene-shifter who watches what you want to do and makes
something else happen. The "something out there" is the structure of
"the way the world works" that has been built up in you by
reorganization and other learning. If there isn't anything regular
"out there", then reorganization won't have regular effects, either.

So, I absolutely refute the notion that all you are doing is
passively observing coincidences independent of yourself, and that
perception of regularities eliminate the need to determine (as a
theorist) where those regularities come from.

... when we're trying to form a theory of human nature, we
have to be more careful, because what we assume is real determines what we
think still needs an explanation.

Absolutely. That's exactly what I've been on about!

If you think that social customs are
real, in the sense of NOT being someone's perceptions of social customs but
actually existing outside the actor, then you don't need to explain how it
is that a person can perceive them, or what role his perceptions play in
determining the idea of society he maintains and controls.

That's the kind of statement that bothers me.

A long time ago, we talked about the different viewpoints involved in
constructing theories like PCT. We talked about the Analyst's
viewpoint, the Actor's viewpoint, the Observer's Viewpoint, the
Theorist's viewpoint (perhaps by other names), and maybe other
viewpoints. You see to me to be mixing viewpoints when you make
statements like the above. The Actor doesn't have to make any
assumption about whether his perceptions relate to a "real reality",
but acts as if they do. The Observer perceives the Actor in the
Actor's environment. The Observer may perceive that Actor to be
acting in conformance with the Observer's perception of the Actor's
cultural norms, or not, and may observe the effects the Actor's
actions have on what the Observer can see of the Actor's inputs. For
the Observer, the Actor and the Actor's environment have the same
level of reality.

The Analyst can go further, and can influence both the Actor (in
simulation) and the Actor's environment. One such procedure has been
given the theological name of "The Test." The Test presumes that the
Actor and the environment have some kind of reality that can be
affected by the actions of the Analyst. The Analyst presumes that it
is possible to influence the input to the Actor's perceptual
processes, and to alter the influence the Actor's actions have on the
Actor's inputs.

The Theorist goes further yet, and enquires how and why the things
observed by the Analyst might be as they are, and what might happen
if the Actor or the Actor's environment were structured thus-and-so,
using what the Theorist has perceived about other situations. That's
what I did with the argument for the necessity of PCT, for example.

Now I'll reword your statement very slightly, so as to make it
something I might go along with: "If the Actor thinks that social
customs are
real, in the sense of NOT being her own perceptions of social customs but
actually existing outside, then she doesn't need to explain how it
is that she can perceive them (though the Theorist very much needs to
do so), or what role her perceptions play in determining the idea of
society she maintains and controls (unless those perceptions of the
society are ones the Actor wants to control).

You simply look
for the effects that social customs have on the actor, and you assume that
all actors in the society are affected by the same customs.

Again, I ask why you would suggest that kind of S-R approach.

This is very
different from assuming that people control in the light of _what they
perceive_ to be actual social customs outside themselves, and therefore
exploring the effects of changing perceptions, and differences in the
behavior of actors relative to the group in which they live.

Of course it's different. But don't forget that the exploration,
right from birth, is in terms of what actions in the context of
interpersonal transactions have what effects on one's perceptions.
That's where reorganization leads to people behaving in culturally
consistent ways.

When I speak of carrying the idea of "it's all perception" to its limit, I
mean what we're talking about here: not exempting any object of observation
from the statement. When we can do that, we have arrived at a starting
point.

Yes, let's get off the starting line. We don't have to have the
starter call a false start every time we get going. I don't think
many of the people involved in this discussion jumped the gun.

Martin

From [Marc Abrams (2004.05.31.1827)]

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1430)]

I think Bill P. (like myself) is mainly resisting the idea that society

and culture are real autonomous agents. But I

guess we're also resisting the idea that perceptions _are_ reality.

You betcha, and imho you're making a huge mistake, huge.

My brother-in-law is a diagnosed schizophrenic, and in conversations I
have had with him, the 'voices' he hears at times are no less real than
mine are.

Marc

Considering how often throughout history even intelligent people have
been proved to be wrong, it is amazing that there are still people who
are convinced that the only reason anyone could possibly say something
different from what they believe is stupidity or dishonesty.

Being smart is what keeps some people from being intelligent.

Thomas Sowell

Don't argue with an idiot; people watching may not be able to tell the
difference.

Anon

I don't approve of political jokes. I've seen too many of them get
elected

Anon

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1600)]

Martin Taylor( 2004.05.31.17.16) --

When we go further than simply saying that, and start talking about
theories like PCT, which assume we work in some "real reality" that
behaves in a way independent of, but influenced by, us, then we get
into areas that warrant discussion.

I think what we get into are areas that warrant modeling and empirical
test.

Yes, let's get off the starting line. We don't have to have the
starter call a false start every time we get going. I don't think
many of the people involved in this discussion jumped the gun.

The problem is that most of the people in this discussion don't seem to
want to study social phenomena using modeling. Talking about culture,
society, language, and economics as though they were "real" in some
sense doesn't explain why we observe these phenomena. What we need are
testable models that explain the phenomena that are observed. Bill
Powers showed how to develop and test such models using the CROWD
program (the behavior of which mimics some of the group behaviors
observed by Clark McPhail). So far, the "experts" in social realities
like language and economics have not bothered to follow his lead.

My guess is that Bill P. is using this debate about the reality of
socio-cultural phenomena to encourage you and his other opponents to
stop arguing and start modeling.

Regards

Rick

···

---
Richard S. Marken
marken@mindreadings.com
Home 310 474-0313
Cell 310 729-1400

From[Bill Williams 31 May 2004 6:10 PM CST]

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1450)]

Martin Taylor (2004.05.31.1641) --

Martin says, and for an ordinarily irenic fellow this is rather
extreme, that Bill Powers' and Rick Marken's ideas are

dangerous,

I have given up on PCT, so it doesn't bother me if PCT theorist
don't wish to apply control theory to cultural theory, still
I find it interesting that Martin reads what Bill Powers and
Rick are saying as an intent label a study of cultural phenomena
as in-approriate within PCT.

in that they imply that the study of culture is not
appropriate within PCT.

There is no such implication in Bill or my remarks.

But, see below where Rick says,

There are no
societies, cultures, languages or dialects in the physics or chemistry
models of reality.

Since as Rick says, the models of physics and chemistry are the models
accepted in PCT then it appears that Martin is right and Rick doesn't
mind being self-contradictory.

What I would like
to see is the study of culture from a PCT perspective.

Like more giant leaps in the wrong direction?

A big part of that perspective is _modeling_.

Like more giant leaps in the wrong direction?

What I would like to see is culture and
society studied using models rather than an endless streams
of words.

Yes, rather than words what Rick likes is giant leaps in
the wrong direction. But, recently he has added magic leaps
closer to reality.

## Then I gues we can expect more magic leaps in the wrong directions.

Societies and cultures, and languages and dialects, are as real (and
as purposive) as rocks.

See my previous post. They are really perceptions.

### No Perceptions aren't really anything, they are just perceptions.

But they are
certainly not really out there, in the world on the other side of our
senses.

## Perceptions don't have "insides" and "outsides." What a goofy idea.

PCT accepts the models of physics and chemistry as the best
current representation of what is really out there.

### But, Rick there is no "really out there." You just don't seem to
get it. All there is, is perception.

There are no
societies, cultures, languages or dialects in the physics or chemistry
models of reality.

### I guess that settles that.

## Would it be a good idea to rush to EBay and speculate in futures on old ## sophistology texts on Logical Positivism?

···

#
# Atomistic individualism-- that's the ticket.
#
# Martin may think Bill Powers' and Rick Marken's position is dangerous.
# And, it may be that, but whether Bill Powers and Rick Marken know it, # and they problably don't this has all been done before. Can everyone say,
# "Logical Positivism?"

Bill Williams

From[Bill Williams 31 May 2004 7:00 PM CST]

[Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.17.16] says, among many other things, that

"... don't forget that the exploration,
right from birth, is in terms of what actions in the context of
interpersonal transactions have what effects on one's perceptions.
That's where reorganization leads to people behaving in culturally
consistent ways.

I would agree with this characterization of the situation a "specimen"
faces in a cultural situation. A specimen has perceptions in a context
that is determined by the interaction of an on-going process carried
on by speciemens ingaged in, ( and Martin's term "transactions" is as
good as any ) transactions between each other and the enviornment.
There is nothing magical involved in considering these transactions
as the context in which speciemens make their choices-- whether as a
result of reorganization or some other process.

It is wrong to attribute to me, any notion of a reified culture. I think it is equally wrong to attribute such a notion to either Martin Taylor or Bruce Nevin.

Bill Powers says,

When I speak of carrying the idea of "it's all perception" to its limit, I
mean what we're talking about here: not exempting any object of observation

"object of observation?" Where did this come from, if "it is all perception?"
Real stuff keeps getting smuggled in all the time. This is the problem with arguing with a solipist.

The only place that has solipcists is a culture. Sollipcists always have company. But solipiicsts are sometimes not very good company because they always insist that you join them in being solipicists.

When Bill Powers talks about carrying the idea that "it's all perception to its limit" I think might be evident that this is an idea that doesn't neccesarily have anything at all to do with developing control theory applications in social theory. The argument is so internally inconsistent and full of smuggled in premises and the result is so weird and lacking in applicablity that what it does is create a tempest-in-a-tea-pot that is going in the future to require a chapter, or a footnote explaining that PCT is _IS NOT_ what is meant by using control theory as a means by which to develop a better social theory.

Bill Williams

[From Bill Powers (2004.05.31.1716 MDT)]

Martin Taylor 2004.05.31.17.16 --

Especially I have no disagreement with the basic premise that our
perceptions are all we know of reality. It is on that basis that I
argue for the equivalent reality of rocks and of cultural artifacts.

That's fine; it's the same point I made. These things are perceptions,
which we can't just assume are facts without going through the formalities
we go through in accepting any other facts into our scientific models. It's
one thing to say that it stands to reason that individuals alter their
behavior in accordance to the societies they live in. It's another to prove
it. Unfortunately, the facts about social systems and their relation to
individuals are among the least reliable that we know of. Gary Cziko found
an article many years ago, a survey of data published in journals relating
to the social sciences. One of the dismal findings was that the average
correlation in all these papers -- and this is for papers that were
peer-reviewed and published -- was 0.26 (as I recall the number). A scatter
plot that illustrates a correlation of 0.26 is barely distinguishable from
a plot of random numbers.

I don't think that there is enough of a relationship there to merit wasting
our time and effort on it. What I do think is worth doing is modeling
individuals, and using the model to create simulations of many people
interacting with environments, and seeing what sorts of relationships
develop. I have no doubt that there will be discernible, provable,
interactions that will explain a lot of social phenomena. There will be
laws of interaction just as there were in the Crowd program. And we will be
able to see, I am confident, how they grow out of properties of individuals
interacting with environments and other individuals. In "we" I include our
descendants, and considering the way the present discussions are going,
maybe I should include _their_ descendants.

Statements such as the one Bill Williams made, that there is no such thing
as an individual, are needlessly provocative and factually on very shaky
ground. We can see individuals, distinguish them from their surroundings,
weigh them, measure them, test their performance in tasks, and infer their
characteristics from models and simulations that produce rather nice
results. We can use the same tests to show that one person's
characteristics are different from another's; the more advanced our testing
becomes, I am confident, the more differences we will be able to
demonstrate. So what is this nonsense about there being no such thing as an
individual? The only way it could hold true would be under some esoteric
and specialized definition of the word "individual" specifically tailored
to allow making such an attention-getting statement. Of course there are
individual human beings, six billion or so of them, alas. No two are
identical, I should think, though I can't prove it.

If you simply assume that any regularity
corresponds to a real regularity outside the brain, then you can forget
about postulating perceptual input functions that (like frequency
filters).impose regularity on variable phenomena.

Why deliberately do that?

It's not deliberate, it's an accidental byproduct. If you think there is
really a stimulus pattern that turned on, then you don't need to explore
the properties of the subject's perceptual system relating to the detection
of light patterns and so forth. The pattern Out There IS the stimulus;
what's to investigate? And they don't, in the laboratories of which I have
known. Bruce Abbott might, but I don't know of anyone else.

If a number of events
lead to the same behavior, you can forget about looking for perceptual
variables they all disturb, and concentrate on finding what is similar
across these "stimuli."

Why forget?

Why, indeed? Because you think the behavior is controlled by the external
events, so different external events (putting out the fire, opening a
window) that have the same behavioral consequence (the subject puts on a
sweater) must have somne physical properties in common. The why is in the
theory you bring to the observations.

When you exempt perceptual phenomena from being
perceptual phenomena, and say instead that they are "real", your whole
explanatory focus changes; you look for external rather than internal causes.

Why so?

Because if they are real phenomena, you don't have to explain why they seem
to have some effect on the subject. You just measure the effect. If you
accept that people see real ghosts, you investigate the environment, not
the people, to find an explanation. You ask how seeing the ghost made the
person feel, not what led the person to think there was a ghost there.

In fact, I would argue quite the contrary to all these statements.

Well, yes, but sincerely or just because you can think of special cases
that indicate something else?

Martin, all this is about the "reality" of relationships among perceptions,
isn't it?

Yes and no. Yes, in the absolute sense that perceptions are all I
have to work with. No in the sense that some of those perceptions are
actually of my intended outputs, and the regularities are the effects
of those outputs on the world.

But you don't see the effect of those outputs on the world; you experience
perceptions affected by those (perceived) outputs. You're still talking
about relationships among perceptions. What do you know about "actually?"

It's rather like the difference
between an observational science like astronomy, where the observer
can't manipulate the stars, and a laboratory science liek chemistry,
where the experimenter can change the constituents of his mixtures
without hindrance from the outer world (other than that the stores
clerk says there isn't any of what the chenist wants).

These are still relationships among perceptions. Think about what you're
trying to establish here. Are you really trying to establish that there is
some class of phenomenon relating to the external world that is NOT a
perception? I don't think you would even try to do that. But it looks as if
you are.

There's an assumption that teh relationship between an intended
action and a change in perception is more than coincidental -- that
something "out there" allows the link to occur, and it isn't simply a
mischievous scene-shifter who watches what you want to do and makes
something else happen. The "something out there" is the structure of
"the way the world works" that has been built up in you by
reorganization and other learning. If there isn't anything regular
"out there", then reorganization won't have regular effects, either.

True, true, and all manner of things are true. But it's still all
perception. You can say anything you want about what is _possibly_ in the
external world, or _plausibly_ in it, or _logically_ in it, but you can't
say what _is_ in it. That would require being able to look it it without
using the perceptions with which you want to compare it. You know that. All
the probablies and possiblies show that you're using brain processes to
formulate propositions from observations of perceptions.

I didn't think we'd be hung up on this for so long, or at all. I thought we
all agreed that the only way the brain knows there even _is_ an external
world, much less what is happening there, is through perceptions, starting
with an array of intensities. And even that is just a model based on
physics and neurology. So why all this effort to get around this
limitation? Doesn't it seem real enough? Why not just accept it as the
truest thing we know, and get on with the business of constructing models
that might possibly tell us about that mostly unknown world on the other
side of the senses? What I'm hearing from you, and Bruce N., and Bill W.,
is "Yes sure, we know only our perceptions and PCT is a model based on that
concept. BUT ...." and then a lot of statements that seem to want to find
things we know are REALLY true. What's wrong with accepting the idea that
modeling is our best and essentially only bet, and just do it? If you have
a good predictive model you have nothing to worry about: testing it will
show that you are right. Of course if you don't have one, there's always
that chance that your generalization may collapse, but that's the name of
the game, isn't it?

So, I absolutely refute the notion that all you are doing is
passively observing coincidences independent of yourself, and that
perception of regularities eliminate the need to determine (as a
theorist) where those regularities come from.

As I completely agree. But if you start out believing that you are looking
at Reality Itself, why would you ever test the proposition that you are
not? Regularities are regularities; if you perceive regularity you perceive
it. I never said you are passively observing anything: you're acting
(making certain easily controllable perceptions occur) in order to observe
the subsequent behavior of other perceptions. You're always working on and
with and through relationships among perceptions

... when we're trying to form a theory of human nature, we
have to be more careful, because what we assume is real determines what we
think still needs an explanation.

Absolutely. That's exactly what I've been on about!

Unfortunately you've disguised it pretty well, or else I really don't
understand what you'e on about.

If you think that social customs are
real, in the sense of NOT being someone's perceptions of social customs but
actually existing outside the actor, then you don't need to explain how it
is that a person can perceive them, or what role his perceptions play in
determining the idea of society he maintains and controls.

That's the kind of statement that bothers me.

A long time ago, we talked about the different viewpoints involved in
constructing theories like PCT. We talked about the Analyst's
viewpoint, the Actor's viewpoint, the Observer's Viewpoint, the
Theorist's viewpoint (perhaps by other names), and maybe other
viewpoints. You see to me to be mixing viewpoints when you make
statements like the above.

All these different roles are only the same person thinking with different
hats on. These roles have to fit together, or they just make a mess. You
can't say that something that is true for the analyst is false for the
Actor, without supplying the link that makes them both true. Apples and
oranges.

The Actor doesn't have to make any
assumption about whether his perceptions relate to a "real reality",
but acts as if they do. The Observer perceives the Actor in the
Actor's environment. The Observer may perceive that Actor to be
acting in conformance with the Observer's perception of the Actor's
cultural norms, or not, and may observe the effects the Actor's
actions have on what the Observer can see of the Actor's inputs. For
the Observer, the Actor and the Actor's environment have the same
level of reality.

While I recognize each role, I think that keeping them separate leads to
serious mistakes. The Observer, for example, who sees only the Actor in the
Actor's environment is ignoring the fact that these are the Observer's
environment, and unless the Observer remains totally passive, the Observer
is also an Actor. There is only one entity here, and separating these
part-functions doesn't help to make that plain. These are all things that
the same person does. The Actor always has a theory and always observes; the
Analyst can't analyze with out observing and acting, and so on. The
classifications are not independent entities. Or if they are, we are
talking about a person with serious problems.

Now I'll reword your statement very slightly, so as to make it
something I might go along with: "If the Actor thinks that social
customs are real, in the sense of NOT being her own perceptions of social
customs but actually existing outside, then she doesn't need to explain
how it is that she can perceive them (though the Theorist very much needs to
do so), or what role her perceptions play in determining the idea of
society she maintains and controls (unless those perceptions of the
society are ones the Actor wants to control).

But what about a theorist who believes, for example, that the self is a
social phenomenon, not a property of an individual? Your speaking
prescriptively, not descriptively. And why doesn't the Actor need to be
concerned about whether the stop light is really green? A mistake could be
fatal, unless the Actor knows that the environment is a simulation. I guess
I don't believe in your entities, any more than I believe in Id. Ego, and
Superego.

You simply look
for the effects that social customs have on the actor, and you assume that
all actors in the society are affected by the same customs.

Again, I ask why you would suggest that kind of S-R approach.

I don't recommend it, I simply propose that people who think social customs
have an objective existence are not likely to do studies of why people
_think_ social customs have objective existence. They are more likely just
to observe the customs, Out There (they think), and see what effects they
have on an individual's behavior.

Yes, let's get off the starting line. We don't have to have the
starter call a false start every time we get going. I don't think
many of the people involved in this discussion jumped the gun.

Well, I have to admit that I haven't studied their models or their data
testing those models very thoroughly. Can you tell me where to find those
things?

Best,

Bill P.

From[Bill Williams 31 May 2004 7:20 PM CST]

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1600)]

Martin Taylor( 2004.05.31.17.16) --

When we go further than simply saying that, and start talking about
theories like PCT, which assume we work in some "real reality" that
behaves in a way independent of, but influenced by, us, then we get
into areas that warrant discussion.

I think what we get into are areas that warrant modeling and empirical
test.

Ricks, foundation for these remarks is an exercise which Bill Powers
described as a "giant leap in the wrong direction." Rick's arguments
here ought to read in this context.

Yes, let's get off the starting line. We don't have to have the
starter call a false start every time we get going. I don't think
many of the people involved in this discussion jumped the gun.

The problem is that most of the people in this discussion don't seem to
want to study social phenomena using modeling.

Ricks, foundation for these remarks is an exercise which Bill Powers
described as a "giant leap in the wrong direction." Rick's arguments
here ought to read in this context.

Talking about culture,
society, language, and economics as though they were "real" in some
sense doesn't explain why we observe these phenomena. What we need are
testable models that explain the phenomena that are observed.

Ricks, foundation for these remarks is an exercise which Bill Powers
described as a "giant leap in the wrong direction." Rick's arguments
here ought to read in this context.

> Bill

Powers showed how to develop and test such models using the CROWD
program (the behavior of which mimics some of the group behaviors
bserved by Clark McPhail).

So far, the "experts" in social realities
like language and economics have not bothered to follow his lead.

Actually the Giffen model was developed well before the Crowd model.
So, you have your lead and lag a bit mixed up.

My guess is that Bill P. is using this debate about the reality of
socio-cultural phenomena to encourage you and his other opponents to
stop arguing and start modeling.

This is another, of the "Did you fuck another pig?" arguments. If you consider what Rick is saying, Rick is guessing that Bill is using a "debate" to get people to "stop arguing." Would the sentence mean the same thing if Rick had said transposed "arguming" with "debate?" Considering if we substitute "talking at people" for both of the terms that Rick uses. Now Powers is "talking at people" at people to get them to stop "talking at people." It is sort of like "shooting people" to stop people "shooting people." It recalls for me my skit on these old folks rolling around in wheelchairs shooting each other. Now Chester is trying to explain why Marshall Dillon is shooting up the town in order to convince people that they all should be solipcists. And, people are leaping every which way-- except that is in the right direction.

Any time Bill Powers wants to stop the argument he can. It is easy for a solipcist to stop arguments if they really want to.

Bill Williams

From Bill Williams 31 May 2004 6:OO PM CST]

  [From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1430)]

  Who says,

  "We can use modeling to determine that the latter comes closest
  to what is really going on."

  According to Bill Powers "Everything is a perception." Whatever
  you do according to Bill Powers all you have are perceptions.

  Rick, however, seems to think that "modeling" to escape from this
  basic truth-- that it is all perception.

  I used to have a lot of fun with quoting Bill Powers, or even more
  fun with misquoting, Bill Powers. Now instead of saying that Rick
  is best at "taking giant leaps in the wrong direction" I can say
  that Rick is taking "magic leaps in the wrong direction."

  If all we have is perception then neither modeling nor anything else
  is going to take us closer to understanding "what is really going on."

  If Rick starts out with a mistake "all we have is what we perceive"
  and then he makes another mistake "modeling can take us closer to
  reality" how am I supposed to score this?

  Bill Williams

[From Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1917)]

Bill Williams (31 May 2004 7:20 PM CST) --

Rick Marken (2004.05.31.1600)--

So far, the "experts" in social realities
like language and economics have not bothered to follow his lead.

Actually the Giffen model was developed well before the Crowd model.
So, you have your lead and lag a bit mixed up.

The Giffen model was written by Bill Powers, not by you. Bill Powers
has said that you helped in the formulation of that model, but based
the "models" you've posted, I would believe that you wrote the plays of
Shakespeare before I would believe that you wrote the Giffen model. You
might have sat on the side and kibbitzed, but that's not the same as
writing them (the models, not the plays). It's clear from the "models"
you've posted that you don't know how to write a computer model and,
based on your reaction to Bill's recent offer to help you write them
properly, you don't want to learn how either. I imagine it's hard to
want to learn when you already know everything.

Regards

Rick

···

---
Richard S. Marken
marken@mindreadings.com
Home 310 474-0313
Cell 310 729-1400