[Hans Blom, 970408b]
(Bill Powers (970331.0030 MST))
... the mere fact that a lot of people accept the textbook
explanations of MCT is no indication at all that these explanations
are error-free. How many people who espouse this approach are simply
passing on the arguments and interpretations they all read in these
same textbooks? ... So who does that leave to keep the theoreticians
honest, but outsiders like me?
As an answer -- and contrast -- to this rather romantic view of
science, some quotes, plucked from a long post by David Longley,
dated 21 Oct 95 10:12:15 GMT, in one of the AI or philosophy
discussion groups. It will be no surprise, I guess, that I side with
the views expressed below. The basic question is: who/what do we
trust more, our own private impressions or the collective results of
science? The quotes do not apply to clinicians only, of course.
'Ultimately, then, clinicians must choose between their own
observations or impressions and the scientific evidence ... Failure
to accept a large and consistent body of scientific evidence over
unvalidated personal observation may be described as a normal human
failing or, in the case of professionals who identify themselves as
scientific, plainly irrational.'
Dawes, Faust & Meehl (1989), Science 243, 1668-1674. Clinical Versus
Actuarial Judgement.
Another quote about personal wisdom versus scientific consensus, here
called "the formula":
'When Shall We Use Our Heads ?'
'The question "When shall we use our heads instead of the formula?"
presupposes that we are about to make a clinical decision at a given
point in time, and must base it upon what is known to us at that
moment. In that context, the question makes perfectly good sense. It
is silly to answer it by saying amicably, "we use both methods, they
go hand in hand". If the formula and your head invariably yield the
same predictions about individuals, you should quit using the more
costly one because it is not adding anything. If they don't always
yield the same prediction - and they clearly don't, as a matter of
empirical fact - then you obviously can't "use both", because you
cannot predict in opposite ways for the same case. If one says then,
"Well, by 'using both,' I mean that we follow the formula except on
special occasions," the problem becomes how to identify the proper
subset of occasions. And this of course amounts to the very question
I am putting. For example, does the formula tell us "Here, use your
head," or do we rely on our heads to tell us this, thus
countermanding the formula?'
P.E. Meehl (1971). When Shall We Use Our Heads instead of the
Formula? Ch 4: PSYCHODIAGNOSIS: SELECTED PAPERS.
A quote about how not a theory but practical results convince:
'An early version of the Green revolution was made possible in the
early 1930s by advances in agricultural technique. The government
duly proceeded to inform the nations' farmers of these techniques by
means of county agricultural agents spouting statistics and
government pamphlets and sat back to await the glowing reports of
increased crop production. No such reports followed and it soon
became clear that farmers were not converting to the new techniques.
Some clever government official then set up a program whereby
government agricultural agents moved in on selected farms and
cultivated the crops along with the farmers, using the new
techniques. Neighbouring farmers watched the crop results and
immediately converted to the techniques.'
Nisbett R.E, Borgida E, Crandall R, and Reed H (1982). Popular
Induction: Information is not necessarily informative.
And a final quote about science as a collective effort:
'Humans did not "make it to the moon" (or unravel the mysteries of
the double helix or deduce the existence of quarks) by trusting the
availability and representativeness heuristics or by relying on the
vagaries of informal data collection and interpretation. On the
contrary, these triumphs were achieved by the use of formal research
methodology and normative principles of scientific inference.
Furthermore, as Dawes (1976) pointed out, no single person could have
solved all the problems involved in such necessarily collective
efforts as space exploration. Getting to the moon was a joint
project, if not of 'idiots savants', at least of savants whose
individual areas of expertise were extremely limited - one savant who
knew a great deal about the propellant properties of solid fuels but
little about the guidance capabilities of small computers, another
savant who knew a great deal about the guidance capabilities of small
computers but virtually nothing about gravitational effects on moving
objects, and so forth. Finally, those savants included people who
believed that redheads are hot-tempered, who bought their last car on
the cocktail-party advice of an acquaintance's brother-in-law, and
whose mastery of the formal rules of scientific inference did not
notably spare them from the social conflicts and personal
disappointments experienced by their fellow humans. The very
impressive results of organised intellectual endeavour, in short,
provide no basis for contradicting our generalizations about human
inferential shortcomings. Those accomplishments are collective, at
least in the sense that we all stand on the shoulders of those who
have gone before; and most of them have been achieved by using
normative principles of inference often conspicuously absent from
everyday life. Most importantly, there is no logical contradiction
between the assertion that people can be very impressively
intelligent on some occasions or in some domains and the assertion
that they can make howling inferential errors on other occasions or
in other domains.'
R. Nisbett and L. Ross (1980). Human Inference: Strategies and
Shortcomings of Social Judgment.
Greetings,
Hans