[From Bruce Abbott (941222.1230 EST)]
Rick Marken (941221.2300)
Bruce Abbott (941221.1030 EST)
In reorganization, do not the consequences of a set of system parameters
(control or failure to control) determine whether those parameters will be
preserved in the system or abandoned in favor of yet other variations?
No. The consequences do NOT determine it. The DIFFERENCE between consequences
and REFERENCE signal determine it. Because reorganization is a closed loop
process, what is actually happening is that the reorganizing system is
determining the consequences (by varying parameters); the consequences do not
determine the parameters. Strange but true in the wonderful world of circular
causality.
Darwin: So you see, like begets like, yet there is variation. In a given
environment, certain variations lead to improved survival, whereas
others lead to premature death or lowered reproductive capability.
I call this process "natural selection." These consequences tend
to produce organisms whose characteristics better adapt them to
their environments.
Marwin: No, no, no! Because evolution is a closed loop process, what is
actually happening is that mutations determine the consequences
(by varying the genes); the consequences do not determine the
genes.
Darwin: Er, well, true, the consequences do not GENERATE the variations,
but I never held that they do. I do not know what generates these
variations, but it appears to be a more-or-less random process.
Over generations, certain variants become more prevalent, and
others less prevalent, owing to the relative reproductive
successes of the organisms that possess them.
Marwin: Ah, so you ADMIT that the consequences do not select the genes of
an INDIVIDUAL organism, yet you continue to believe in this
evolution thing. O.K., provide a diagram showing how consequences
can set the gene structure of a single organism.
Darwin: [sighs, pulls pocket watch out of his breast pocket, looks at it,
and puts the watch away] Listen, I'd love to continue this
conversation, but it's time I got back to work. Nice talking with
you, have a nice holiday. [turns abruptly and walks away]
Again you have managed to find some "flaw" to pick apart rather than taking an
objective look at the argument. To wit:
No. The consequences do NOT determine it. The DIFFERENCE between consequences
and REFERENCE signal determine it.
This is a mere definitional problem. I view the "consequence" AS the effect
of the behavior on the error signal, which IS a change in the difference
between consequences [as you define them] and reference signal. I've said
this repeatedly, to no avail. Thus my description IS your description. The
assertions you make in the rest of your post are predicated on this
misunderstanding, especially
This will seem puzzling until you learn how a control system works. The
best way to do that is by running simulations of control systems
This is very strange. Too bad you are not able to actually run my demo and
see for yourself that it represents a beautiful example of a two-level control
system. Doesn't it strike you as odd that someone can WRITE simulations of
perceptual control systems without having a clue as to how they work?
[Probably not. I'm sure you will find an explanation that allows you to keep
up your perception that I do not understand them. It seems to be a highly-
valued reference level for you and thus strongly defended.]
Rick Marken (941218.1800)
Bruce Abbott (941218.1650 EST)
Rick, I accepted feedback-regulated
control as a general principle of behavior (and rejected the
reinforcement model) before I ever heard of Bill Powers and his book.
I can't think of any sense in which control could be
described as "feedback regulated"; if anything, control REGULATES
FEEDBACK, where feedback is the perceptual consequence of the
controller's own output.
Ah, more sand in the gears. This is a common description of the process, in
which "feedback-regulated" indicates the TYPE of control. Although in PCT,
"control" apparently refers to one, and only one, process (thus, no need for
the qualifier), in other contexts it also refers to open-loop situations, as
when a clock trips a relay that starts up your coffee-maker in the morning.
The clock "controls" the coffee-maker in that it has the ability to turn it
on, but the circuitry does not receive any sensory confirmation that the
coffee-maker is actually working after the relay signal has been sent.
Regards,
Bruce