scientific fact regarding coercion

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.0952 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.0649 MDT)

Bruce Gregory (991116.0510 EST)--

>I think Ed's biggest mistake was associating his program
with PCT. All he
>really needs from PCT is the concept that children and teachers are
>intentional agents.

Odd that you should say that. Ed Ford, Tom Bourbon, and Tim
Carey seem to
have come to exactly the opposite conclusion. They say that
teachers and
administrators who really get into RTP always want to learn
more about PCT,
recognizing that it is the real justification for the
program.

I don't find this the least surprising considering the individuals who
find this result. A proper test would be an implementation of RTP with
_no_ mention of PCT (except as the scientific model behind the program).
Most airline passengers do not feel the need to understand the
engineering that when into the plane. They are content to know that such
engineering did indeed occur. I suspect teachers and administrators
resemble airline passengers more that the represent the folks on CSGnet.

They say
that the schools where the people fail to catch on to PCT are
the ones most
likely to misapply RTP. They are more heavily into teaching
PCT than ever
before. Tom Bourbon told me all this in a recent friendly
phone call (in
case Marc Abrams was wondering whatever came of his suggestion).

Tom is obviously biased. A good man, but hardly the person to conduct a
proper double blind test.

Bruce Gregory

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.0957 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.0529 MDT)

I'm not sure what your statement means. Do you mean that you
realize that
nobody can actually "give" another person a choice, or do you
mean you're
not in favor of leaving a child any alternatives to choose
among? Obviously,
there is a great deal of difference between these views.

Agreed. My suspicion is that it doesn't matter whether or not you tell
the child you are giving him a choice. The goal is to allow the student
to become aware of the consequences of his or her actions, the better to
achieve his or her goals whatever they may be. The options are simply a
description of the alternatives provided by the social world of school.

Bruce Gregory

[From Rick Marken (991116.0810)]

Me:

That was my point, Bruce. They are equivalent! They both are
instructions for coercion. The only difference is that Ed's
description ("formulation") blames the coercion on the kid.
My description blames coercion on the person who is being
asked to carry it out: the teacher.

Bruce Gregory (991116.0451 EST)

You are not to be blamed for speeding.

Yes I am. If I am controlling for speeding. I am not to be
blamed for the cop giving me a ticket because I am not
controlling for getting the ticket; the cop is to be blamed
because he intends to give the ticket. The child in RTP
can be blamed for disrupting if that's what the kid intends;
but he can't be blamed for being sent to the RTC room; the
teacher is responsible for doing that.

See, I _do_ understand, Rick.

Actually, I see that you don't understand at all.

Me:

Is there anything about the RTP program that you think
could be improved? How about the way it is described
[see Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)]?

Bruce:

I completely agree with his appraisal:

Then why are you disagreeing with me? Bill and I are
saying the same thing: "giving a choice" is coercive,
not respectful; attributing one's own controlling to
the controllee is dishonest. Don't you agree?

Bruce Gregory (991116.0510 EST)--

I think Ed's biggest mistake was associating his program
with PCT.

If you read the literature on RTP you will see that PCT is
the main thing that distinguishes RTP from Glasser's school
discipline program (at least, as described, if not as
practiced). So if you think it's a mistake to base RTP on
PCT (and it may be, since Ed and Tom won't attend CSG meetings
anymore or list the CSG web site at the RTP web site) why
not tell Ed and Tom?

Bill Powers (991116.0541 MDT) --

The difference between these two examples is that in the second
example, there is no person responsible for the fact that if you
step out the window you will fall. That's a result of natural
law and is non-negotiable.

Bruce Gregory (991116.1012 EST)--

Indeed. But Rick feels the desirable course is to negotiate
with state troopers. I treat them like laws of nature.

Rick feels that the driver is responsible for speeding
and the trooper is responsible for giving the ticket; just
as, in the RTP situation, the kid is responsible for
disrupting and the teacher is responsible for sending the
kid to the RTC room. The speeding driver has not "chosen"
to get a ticket; the disruptive kid has not "chosen" to
go to the RTC room.

Bruce Abbott (991116.1030 EST)

the RTP program is a _wonderful_ example of a properly designed
and implemented program of behavior modification, even though
its developers and proponents do not understand that fact and
believe that they have invented a new wheel.

The _description_ of the RTP program is, indeed, a description of
a properly designed and implemented behavior modification program;
that was Bill's point [Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)]. Obviously,
to the extent that RTP (and other behavior modification programs)
work they are doing something quite different than what they
say they are doing. If they actually practiced what they preached
(strict enforcement of contingencies) there would be continuous,
violent conflict (as there is in conventional schools where
behavior modification is implemented blindly -- ie. without
awareness of or sensitivity to the volitional nature of the
systems whose behavior is being "modified").

When you understand that fact, PCT will finally have a chance
to make some

I agree. When psychologists see (as you have) that PCT is
reinforcement theory, then PCT will make it.

Best

Rick

···

--
Richard S. Marken Phone or Fax: 310 474-0313
Life Learning Associates mailto: rmarken@earthlink.net
http://home.earthlink.net/~rmarken

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.1012 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.0541 MDT)]

The difference between these two examples is that in the
second example,
there is no person responsible for the fact that if you step
out the window
you will fall. That's a result of natural law and is non-negotiable.

Indeed. But Rick feels the desirable course is to negotiate with state
troopers. I treat them like laws of nature.

I could state a rule that if you disagree with me on this
matter, you flunk
out of PCT and must leave the net. So if, knowing the rule, you still
disagree with me, I could say "I see you have chosen to leave
the net" and
cut you off (not that I can actually do that). But wouldn't
that outcome
still be my responsibility?

Responsibility is a interesting idea. In my experience, it expands your
domain of control to adopt the view that you are responsible and
diminishes the domain of control to you adopt the viewpoint that someone
else is responsible. Trying to thrust responsibility on someone who is
not eager to accept it is a good recipe for failure.

It was I who made the rule, and I
who decided
what your action meant, and I who carried out the
consequence. I can try to
make it seem that it was all your doing, but that ignores the
question of
who made the rule or insists on applying it. Your only sin
was in doing the
thing I didn't want you to do. But I can make it seem that
not only was
this sin all your fault, but its consequences, created by me,
were also
your fault since (I am trying to claim) they follow from the
act just as
inevitably and impersonally as the law of gravity makes you
fall if you
step out the window.

Indeed. Fault implies a moral judgement. Responsibility simply describes
agency. We like to use the word responsibility to imply fault, but I
don't have much evidence that this ploy works very well.

If I do not like the consequences of my choices, I must first
find out why
the consequences were bad before I can do something rational
about them. In
the case of your disagreeing with me, with the consequence of being
expelled from CSGnet, would you accept that consequence the
way you would
accept the consequences of failing to fill the gas tank and
thereby running
out of gas?

Why not?

I think not; I think you might turn to other
people on the net
and complain that I'm being arbitrary and assuming a control
over you that
I don't have. You might suggest that I leave the net instead.
You would
quite possibly tell me to take my rule and stuff it.

None of these are likely to bring me any closer to my goal, don't you
agree?

I'm not sure we're talking about the right subject here. I
would assume
that you would not go along with my arbitrary rule-making,
and would simply
refuse to take the blame for the consequences I made up for
you, because we
are both adults and presumably equals. I have no right to
make rules for
you, or to impose consequences on you when you break them.

You might not enjoy playing chess with me if I tried to negotiate the
rules. After all, the rules of chess are _completely_ arbitrary. We are
mature adults. Let's talk about how my king should be able to get out of
the trap you just sprung.

If
I were to
demand that you behave in a certain way, and state what I
would do if you
didn't comply, you would at least expect me to take responsibility for
making the demand and for doing whatever I described as the
consequence.

Not necessarily. You act as an intentional agent whether or not you
"take responsibility". You might be a more effective agent if you "take
responsibility" but there is nothing I can do about that. Telling you
that you are responsible seems likely to have no effect at all on your
actions.

If
I told you I'd smash your windshield for breaking my rule,
and then (after
you broke the rule and your windshield suffered) I told you
that you caused
the windshield to be smashed, I think you would still hold me and my
insurance company responsible, and have plenty of legal and
moral backing.

In this case responsibility is defined legally. I would proceed
accordingly. I have no vested interest, however, in your beating your
breast and saying mea culpa, mea culpa.

We're really talking about how adults should treat children,
aren't we?

Yes. At least that is my understanding of RTP. Children first need to
get around in a world filled with rules they had no part in making. Only
later will they be able to follow or break these rules and be held
accountable for the consequences.

Bruce Gregory

[From Bruce Abbott (991116.1030 EST)]

Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT) --

Notice that the children are not asked what they want to do; they are given
two choices and asked which one they choose (one is to leave home,
according to the above). "Neither one" is not an allowed choice.

Ed sees a key aspect of the process as consisting of taking away important
privileges like being with friends or family and then restoring them when
the child makes a committment to follow the rules.

In chapter 8 and chapter 9, it is clear that Ed takes a strictly S-R view
toward making children behave: deprive them of something they value, then
give it back when they agree to obey the rules. From this and many other
examples, I concluded long ago that if Ed's program works well (and I
believe it does), it works in spite of the reasons he gives and the methods
he proposes.

I don't want to rub this in. Ed's program is a marvel; I simply don't
believe it works for the reasons he gives. When actually interacting with
people, Ed doesn't try to control them; . . .

Tom Bourbon is ever-present in Ed's presentations, and supplements his
talks with his own teaching of PCT principles. Tim Carey, when he is
present, does the same. People who learn Ed's methods learn much more than
he teaches in words; they learn from watching how he operates, and they
learn PCT at the same time from the best teachers in the business. So what
they learn is not necessarily what Ed writes down in his books and
demonstrates in presentations.

The actual program, as it is carried out in practice, is not necessarily
the same program that Ed describes in his books.

I suspect that the actual program is exactly the program that Ed describes
in his books. Perhaps the most important element is the rapport established
between the kids and the adults with whom they interact (teachers, parents,
etc.). When a kids screws up (according to the adults' standards), the
adults do not become angry and behave as if the kid were hated; rather, the
adults remain reassuring of their love/liking/respect for the child, explain
why they must (reluctantly) remove the child from the group, explain the
conditions for reentry into the group, and then carry out the removal. The
child learns that his/her behavior is the problem that is leading to the
child's removal, not the adult's dislike for the child, or some perverse joy
the adult gets from punishing the child.

Another important element is that the contingencies (rules) are made clear,
and the child is reminded of those contingencies when the first infraction
occurs. For many of these children, I suspect, a major problem is that they
have difficulty noticing or remembering, at the time that they are breaking
a rule, what the consequence of that behavior is going to be. (Their
attention is focused elsewhere.) The reminder helps to strengthen the link,
so that when the child thinks about or begins to engage in that behavior
again, he or she is more likely to be stopped short by the realization that
the behavior is going to produce a certain unwanted consequence.

Also important is the fact that the time is taken to explain to the child
what the contingencies are, and why the adults find it necessary to impose
them, at a time when the child is calm and able to understand the adult's
reasons. As a result, the adult's actions when the child breaks the rules
are seen by the child as reasonable rather than as arbitrary and capricious.
This is especially so since the child has participated in developing the
plan of action.

Removal of the child serves three ends: first, it ends the disruption to
others created by the child; second, by cutting the child off from social
contact with friends and trusted adults, it places the child in an emotional
state (unhappiness) that the child would rather avoid, and can avoid in the
future by inhibiting the behavior that brings about the removal; third, it
cuts the child off from receiving attention and other rewards for the
unwanted behavior.

The idea that these contingencies are not the reason for the success of RTP,
and that some hidden element, provided in some mysterious way by trained
PCTers, strikes me as incredible.

None of the elements of RTP that I have outlined above _should be_
incompatible with PCT (although as characterized in this forum it is always
depicted as incompatible). At the same time, the RTP program is a
_wonderful_ example of a properly designed and implemented program of
behavior modification, even though its developers and proponents do not
understand that fact and believe that they have invented a new wheel.

When you understand that fact, PCT will finally have a chance to make some
real inroads.

Regards,

Bruce A.

[From Bruce Abbott (991116.1230 EST)]

Rick Marken (991116.0810) --

The _description_ of the RTP program is, indeed, a description of
a properly designed and implemented behavior modification program;
that was Bill's point [Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)].

And _my_ point is that the description is correct.

Obviously,
to the extent that RTP (and other behavior modification programs)
work they are doing something quite different than what they
say they are doing.

That is not at all obvious; in fact, it is incorrect.

If they actually practiced what they preached
(strict enforcement of contingencies) there would be continuous,
violent conflict (as there is in conventional schools where
behavior modification is implemented blindly -- ie. without
awareness of or sensitivity to the volitional nature of the
systems whose behavior is being "modified").

I suspect that they _do_ practice what they preach. If so, then your
prediction, presumably based on PCT, is not only wrong, it is _dramatically_
wrong. The only evidence you have that they do _not_ practice what they
preach is that if they did, your prediction would be wrong. Bring me some
concrete evidence that they do other than they preach, and we'll talk. As
it stands, you are merely engaging in circular reasoning -- and giving voice
to your own prejudices.

When you understand that fact, PCT will finally have a chance
to make some inroads.

I agree. When psychologists see (as you have) that PCT is
reinforcement theory, then PCT will make it.

Oh, pleeeeze, spare the stupidities.

I am not claiming that PCT is reinforcement theory. What I _do_ claim is
that you and Bill have constructed a straw-man cartoon version of
reinforcement theory that bears little resemblance to it as actually
understood by its practitioners, from which follows your dire predictions as
to the consequences of implementing these principles in a program of
behavior modification. The success of Ford's program shows these
predictions are startlingly incorrect, which fact should occasion some
serious rethinking on the part of any PCT theorist who is concerned about
the validity of his assumptions, or of his deductions from those
assumptions. Pretending that Ford's program works despite, rather than
because of, its implementation of behavior modification principles, owing to
a hidden ingredient (PCT), is another way to deal with your dilemma, of
course, but reasonable people should find that an extremely unsatisfactory
solution.

What this suggests to me is that if your PCT-based analysis says that Ford's
approach can't work if implemented as Ford describes, then there is
something very amiss with your PCT-based analysis.

Regards,

Bruce

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.0451 EST)]

Rick Marken (991115.2040)]

> That was my point, Bruce. They are equivalent! They both are
> instructions for coercion. The only difference is that Ed's
> description ("formulation") blames the coercion on the kid.
> My description blames coercion on the person who is being
> asked to carry it out: the teacher.

You are not to be blamed for speeding. The trooper is to be blamed for
giving you a ticket. All you want to do is to drive at any speed you like.
Since you live in a coercive system, no one asks you what you want. They
simply give you "choices" where neither alternative takes into account
_your_ goals. See, I _do_ understand, Rick.

I have been straining not to respond to your posts in this thread. This is
just to convoluted and unreasonable to let pass. Rick never said he was not
responsible for speeding. What he said, and what anyone without an ax to
grind could see, is that he did not choose to recieve a ticket, go to court,
pay a fine, perhaps pay an increased insurance premium, and so on. Just so,
the child has chosen to do what he has done, but not necessarily to leave
the classroom. Sometimes it is necessary to to have a coercive elements in
a program, at least within our current understanding; refusing to admit that
will not make the program no-coercixe, but will make the description
dishonest and may make it harder to make efforts to reduce the degree of
coercion involved.

···

On Tue, Nov 16, 1999 at 04:51:55AM -0500, Bruce Gregory wrote:

> Every one of your posts on the topic of RTP. I have never
> heard you criticize any aspect of RTP. But I may be wrong.
> Maybe we've just never touched on those aspects of RTP with
> which you have a problem. Is there anything about the RTP
> program that you think could be improved? How about the way
> it is described [see Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)]?

I completely agree with his appraisal:

> I think my view of the RTP program is balanced, realistic, and fair. I'm
> not a PR flack promoting the program, and I think that my attempt to see
it
> as it really is makes my support of it more, not less, credible. I would
> tell any school system to put the RTP program into effect immediately.
Even
> if it isn't perfect, it is far and away the best school discipline program
> anywhere.

Bruce Gregory

--
Samuel Spence Saunders, Ph.D.
ssaunde@ibm.net

[From Bill Powers (991116.1158 MDT)]

Bruce Gregory (991116.1012 EST)]

Responsibility is a interesting idea. In my experience, it expands your
domain of control to adopt the view that you are responsible and
diminishes the domain of control to you adopt the viewpoint that someone
else is responsible. Trying to thrust responsibility on someone who is
not eager to accept it is a good recipe for failure.

Responsibility simply describes
agency. We like to use the word responsibility to imply fault, but I
don't have much evidence that this ploy works very well.

This adds up, for me, to the teacher admits agency, ideally, in the
decision that the child must go the to RTC. The child admits agency,
ideally, in creating the disruption. To tell the child that the child chose
to go to the RTC is simply a factual mistake. Whoever made the rule decided
that on the second infraction, the child would be sent to the RTC. The
teacher enforces the rule. Why is such a simple and truthful way of putting
it arousing your opposition?

In
the case of your disagreeing with me, with the consequence of being
expelled from CSGnet, would you accept that consequence the
way you would accept the consequences of failing to fill the gas tank and
thereby running out of gas?

Why not?

I see you've chosen not to be serious about this discussion, so let's
abanmdon it.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bill Powers (991116.1212 MDT)]

Bruce Abbott (991116.1030 EST)--

I suspect that the actual program is exactly the program that Ed describes
in his books.

That's your brilliant argument, a simple contradiction of what I said?

Perhaps the most important element is the rapport established
between the kids and the adults with whom they interact (teachers, parents,
etc.). When a kids screws up (according to the adults' standards), the
adults do not become angry and behave as if the kid were hated; rather, the
adults remain reassuring of their love/liking/respect for the child, explain
why they must (reluctantly) remove the child from the group, explain the
conditions for reentry into the group, and then carry out the removal. The
child learns that his/her behavior is the problem that is leading to the
child's removal, not the adult's dislike for the child, or some perverse joy
the adult gets from punishing the child.

That is not how Ed describes his program; it's your way of describing it so
it sounds like something you would approve of. If you saw what actually
goes on in a good RTP program, it would be quite like what you describe.
But if you had only Ed's writings to rely on, you would get quite a
different picture. I even said so in the forward I wrote for Ed's
discipline book. Nobody gave me any flack for it.

Another important element is that the contingencies (rules) are made clear,
and the child is reminded of those contingencies when the first infraction
occurs.

Right. Normal people call them consequences, but I get the idea. However,
you have to admit that the child is being misinformed about the causes of
these consequences. The child is the cause of the second infraction, but
the teacher's enforcement of the RTP program's rules is what sends the
child to the RTC. If the child refuses to go and presents a physical
problem, the local security people are called in, or the police when the
school has no security force (according to Ed's description, that is. In
real RTP schools this is essentially never done).

For many of these children, I suspect, a major problem is that they
have difficulty noticing or remembering, at the time that they are breaking
a rule, what the consequence of that behavior is going to be. (Their
attention is focused elsewhere.)

Sounds reasonable, under anyone's theory.

Also important is the fact that the time is taken to explain to the child
what the contingencies are, and why the adults find it necessary to impose
them, at a time when the child is calm and able to understand the adult's
reasons. As a result, the adult's actions when the child breaks the rules
are seen by the child as reasonable rather than as arbitrary and capricious.
This is especially so since the child has participated in developing the
plan of action.

You're indulging in imagination. Ed speaks very little about explaining why
the adults impose the rules, and he admonishes teachers not to listen to
the child's reasons for the actions, saying this will only encourage them
to make excuses. It is not the children's place to question the rules. His
focus is strictly on obeying the rules, and if they are broken putting the
child in a position where it is necessary to agree to obey them and make a
plan for obeying them, or be sent home.

Of course in practice, the RTC teacher does try to find out why the student
broke the rules, and listens to the "excuses" at least enough to know
whether the student is taking responsibility for his or her own actions. In
the most successful of the schools, the people in charge of the program
spend a lot of time discussing the rules with the children, and working
with the children to get agreements on a set of rules the children can
accept. None of that is described in any of Ed's writings; it was invented
by others carrying out his program. Ed just says "They know what the rules
are. They know right from wrong."

Removal of the child serves three ends: first, it ends the disruption to
others created by the child; second, by cutting the child off from social
contact with friends and trusted adults, it places the child in an emotional
state (unhappiness) that the child would rather avoid, and can avoid in the
future by inhibiting the behavior that brings about the removal; third, it
cuts the child off from receiving attention and other rewards for the
unwanted behavior.

Yes, that's what Ed seems to believe, too. But he claims he does not
deliberately hurt the child.

The idea that these contingencies are not the reason for the success of RTP,
and that some hidden element, provided in some mysterious way by trained
PCTers, strikes me as incredible.

I guess you really don't understand what the "hidden element" is.

None of the elements of RTP that I have outlined above _should be_
incompatible with PCT (although as characterized in this forum it is always
depicted as incompatible). At the same time, the RTP program is a
_wonderful_ example of a properly designed and implemented program of
behavior modification, even though its developers and proponents do not
understand that fact and believe that they have invented a new wheel.

Tell that to all the behavior-mod people whose programs have been replaced
in schools by RTP after crashing failures.

It's at times like these that it becomes plain to me that your whole
purpose in being part of these discussions is to defend your profession
against anything that threatens to change it beliefs. You have accepted the
behaviorist position hook, line, sinker, and pole, and it is simply too
late for you to change your mind. I'm sorry. You're a good man, and as
smart as they come. But your investment in the past is too much to overcome.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.1611 EST)]

Rick Marken (991116.0810)

Yes I am. If I am controlling for speeding.

Suppose you are _not_ controlling for speeding. In the same way the
student may _not_ be controlling for disrupting. Suppose both speeding
and disrupting are side effects rather than CVs. I suspect they are in
most cases.

I am not to be
blamed for the cop giving me a ticket because I am not
controlling for getting the ticket; the cop is to be blamed
because he intends to give the ticket.

In general, one is to be blamed for controlling whatever variable one is
controlling.

The child in RTP
can be blamed for disrupting if that's what the kid intends;

If it is a side effect, the kid presumably cannot be blame for
disrupting. Is that what you meant to say?

but he can't be blamed for being sent to the RTC room; the
teacher is responsible for doing that.

O.K. The teacher is blamed for whatever the teacher intends.

> See, I _do_ understand, Rick.

Actually, I see that you don't understand at all.

O.K.

Me:

> Is there anything about the RTP program that you think
> could be improved? How about the way it is described
> [see Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)]?

Bruce:

> I completely agree with his appraisal:

Then why are you disagreeing with me? Bill and I are
saying the same thing: "giving a choice" is coercive,
not respectful; attributing one's own controlling to
the controllee is dishonest. Don't you agree?

Of course. How could anyone disagree?

Rick feels that the driver is responsible for speeding

Only if the driver was controlling for speeding.

and the trooper is responsible for giving the ticket;

Only if the trooper was controlling for giving a ticket.

just
as, in the RTP situation, the kid is responsible for
disrupting

Only if disrupting is the CV.

and the teacher is responsible for sending the

kid to the RTC room.

Yes, assuming the teacher was controlling for sending the kid to RTC
room.

The speeding driver has not "chosen"
to get a ticket; the disruptive kid has not "chosen" to
go to the RTC room.

What does "choose" in the HPCT model?

The _description_ of the RTP program is, indeed, a description of
a properly designed and implemented behavior modification program;
that was Bill's point [Bill Powers (991115.1115 MDT)]. Obviously,
to the extent that RTP (and other behavior modification programs)
work they are doing something quite different than what they
say they are doing. If they actually practiced what they preached
(strict enforcement of contingencies) there would be continuous,
violent conflict (as there is in conventional schools where
behavior modification is implemented blindly -- ie. without
awareness of or sensitivity to the volitional nature of the
systems whose behavior is being "modified").

Is the Masspike, in your view, the scene of continuous violent conflict
because the troopers are "without awareness of or sensitivity to the
volitional nature" of the commuters?

Bruce Gregory

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.1622 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.1158 MDT)

This adds up, for me, to the teacher admits agency, ideally, in the
decision that the child must go the to RTC. The child admits agency,
ideally, in creating the disruption. To tell the child that
the child chose
to go to the RTC is simply a factual mistake.

O.K. Can you explain to me how choice is modeled in HPCT? I am
increasingly aware that I have no idea of the model you and Rick are
using.

Whoever made
the rule decided
that on the second infraction, the child would be sent to the RTC. The
teacher enforces the rule. Why is such a simple and truthful
way of putting
it arousing your opposition?

I'm simply trying to understand why this point is such a life and death
matter for you and Rick. Perhaps when I see the PCT model of choice it
will become clear to me.

I see you've chosen not to be serious about this discussion, so let's
abandon it.

I have no idea what precipitated this. Care to give me a clue?

Bruce Gregory

[From Rick Marken (991116.1430)]

Me:

Yes I am [responsible for speeding]. If I am controlling for speeding.

Bruce Gregory (991116.1611 EST) --

Suppose you are _not_ controlling for speeding.

Then I am controlling for (and responsible for) something else.
But I am not controlling for getting a ticket; so I am not
responsible for being stopped and being given a ticket; the
policeman is responsible for giving me the ticket.

In general, one is to be blamed for controlling whatever
variable one is controlling.

Right! Though "blame" seems a but judgmental; I would rather
say that one should be "held responsible" only for the behavior
of the variables one is controlling.

If it is a side effect, the kid presumably cannot be blame for
disrupting. Is that what you meant to say?

Yes. If you must blame the kid for (hold the kid responsible
for) anything, blame him for what he is controlling for that,
as a side effect, is causing the disruption.

O.K. The teacher is blamed for whatever the teacher intends.

Yes. The teacher (not the disruptive student) intends that the
disruptive student be in the RTC after the second disruption.

What does "choose" [mean] in the HPCT model?

Setting a reference for a particular state of a perception.

Me:

If they [RTP practitioners] actually practiced what they preached
(strict enforcement of contingencies) there would be continuous,
violent conflict

Bruce:

Is the Masspike, in your view, the scene of continuous violent
conflict because the troopers are "without awareness of or
sensitivity to the volitional nature" of the commuters?

I believe the Masspike is not the scene of continuous, violent
conflict because people generally perceive enforcement of traffic
rules as being legitimate; people have agreed to drive according
to these rules (probably because they seem sensible) and enforcement
of the rules is fairly lax (every person who briefly exceeds the
speed limit is not instantly stopped and ticketed). It's a lot like
the way RTP is practiced (rather than described).

Best

Rick

···

--
Richard S. Marken Phone or Fax: 310 474-0313
Life Learning Associates mailto: rmarken@earthlink.net
http://home.earthlink.net/~rmarken

[From Bruce Abbott (991116.1720 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.1212 MDT)]

Bruce Abbott (991116.1030 EST)--

I suspect that the actual program is exactly the program that Ed describes
in his books.

That's your brilliant argument, a simple contradiction of what I said?

No, that's my thesis. If you want the argument, I can present it: Because
Ed Ford developed the program and has seen it working in practice, it is
likely that he knows what the effective elements of the program are, and has
stated them in his book. Ford could be wrong, but I'd want to see evidence
of that before rejecting his claims. Your even more brilliant
counterargument is that you don't believe that a program designed and
implemented along those principles could work.

That is not how Ed describes his program; it's your way of describing it so
it sounds like something you would approve of. If you saw what actually
goes on in a good RTP program, it would be quite like what you describe.
But if you had only Ed's writings to rely on, you would get quite a
different picture.

Well I haven't read Ed's book and have had only the descriptions offered on
CSGnet to go on. I'm glad that from your point of view, what actually goes
on is quite like my description.

Another important element is that the contingencies (rules) are made clear,
and the child is reminded of those contingencies when the first infraction
occurs.

Right. Normal people call them consequences, but I get the idea. However,
you have to admit that the child is being misinformed about the causes of
these consequences. The child is the cause of the second infraction, but
the teacher's enforcement of the RTP program's rules is what sends the
child to the RTC.

I don't think I have to admit anything of the sort. If I pull the bottom
can from a stack of soup cans and the cans all tumble down, would you say
that I am the cause of the removal of the first can but that the stock clerk
who arranged the stack is the cause of the rest of the cans crashing down?
I'd say that the clerk set up the _conditions_ such that my removing the
bottom would have that consequence, but as to them actually crashing down,
that's _my_ doing. Similarly, the adult arranges the consequences for
misbehavior of the child and explains those consequences to the child, but
it is the child's actions that bring about those consequences, and in that
specific sense the child is responsible for their occurrence.

Also important is the fact that the time is taken to explain to the child
what the contingencies are, and why the adults find it necessary to impose
them, at a time when the child is calm and able to understand the adult's
reasons. As a result, the adult's actions when the child breaks the rules
are seen by the child as reasonable rather than as arbitrary and capricious.
This is especially so since the child has participated in developing the
plan of action.

You're indulging in imagination. Ed speaks very little about explaining why
the adults impose the rules, and he admonishes teachers not to listen to
the child's reasons for the actions, saying this will only encourage them
to make excuses. It is not the children's place to question the rules. His
focus is strictly on obeying the rules, and if they are broken putting the
child in a position where it is necessary to agree to obey them and make a
plan for obeying them, or be sent home.

O.K. Again, I'm going by my recollection (perhaps somewhat faulty) of
CSGnet descriptions. How does the child learn what the contingencies are?
(I would bet that the adult who explains the rules and the consequences of
breaking them offers some justification for them -- "Johnny, we just can't
have a child distracting the rest of us from what we are trying to get done
here. I'm sure you understand.")

Of course in practice, the RTC teacher does try to find out why the student
broke the rules, and listens to the "excuses" at least enough to know
whether the student is taking responsibility for his or her own actions. In
the most successful of the schools, the people in charge of the program
spend a lot of time discussing the rules with the children, and working
with the children to get agreements on a set of rules the children can
accept.

O.K., this is close to what I had in mind.

The idea that these contingencies are not the reason for the success of RTP,
and that some hidden element, provided in some mysterious way by trained
PCTers, strikes me as incredible.

I guess you really don't understand what the "hidden element" is.

I understand what you _think_ the "hidden element" is. I'm just not
convinced that it is the reason why the program is so successful. You
certainly haven't provided any evidence that it is.

None of the elements of RTP that I have outlined above _should be_
incompatible with PCT (although as characterized in this forum it is always
depicted as incompatible). At the same time, the RTP program is a
_wonderful_ example of a properly designed and implemented program of
behavior modification, even though its developers and proponents do not
understand that fact and believe that they have invented a new wheel.

Tell that to all the behavior-mod people whose programs have been replaced
in schools by RTP after crashing failures.

In as much as RTP, as you have described here, sounds like a terriffic
implementation of behavior analysis principles, this would suggest that the
previous failures are either (a) apocryphal (the previous "program" was no
program at all, just the usual student-teacher interactions, with
predictable results) or (b) were engineered by incompetent practitioners.
As RTP demonstrates, when it's done right, it works.

It's at times like these that it becomes plain to me that your whole
purpose in being part of these discussions is to defend your profession
against anything that threatens to change it beliefs. You have accepted the
behaviorist position hook, line, sinker, and pole, and it is simply too
late for you to change your mind. I'm sorry. You're a good man, and as
smart as they come. But your investment in the past is too much to overcome.

Well, if you don't like the message, trash the messenger, is that it?

My purpose in being part of these discussions is to resolve, to the extent
possible, a number of outstanding difficulties I continue to perceive with
PCT and with certain pronouncements that have been made, supposedly based on
PCT, that just don't jibe with certain facts of which I am aware. Fro my
perspective, I've had a different set of experiences than you, and these
experiences have opened my eyes to a set of possibilities that you,
apparently, are unwilling or unable to grasp, for whatever reason. From my,
probably unique, perspective I can see how certain principles from behavior
analysis and others from control theory can be unified into a coherent
theory of behavior with considerable power. I know why you believe that
these principles are incompatible and I think I understand why this belief
is incorrect. Unfortunately, I haven't had much success in convincing you
of this. It is all too easy for you to simply explain this conflict away by
assuming that I am a victim of my own past and, like the "old school" of
Kuhnian lore, will simply have to retire or pass away to make way for the new.

What isn't readily apparent from my interactions on CSGnet is that I am even
more troubled by many of the standard assumptions/conclusions of many EABers
in particular and research psychologists in general. I agree with you that
the whole damned field is a sorry mess, and is unlikely to improve any time
soon.

Example: An undergraduate test on learning that came out not too long ago
reasserts the following:

  Environment-behavior relations provide a natural science-based
  account of phenomena that would otherwise be taken as evidence
  of the purposive or goal-directed character of behavior. . . .
  The outcome of the selection process is that the learner acts
  _as if_ he had "purpose," "intelligence," and the like, but these
  inferred characteristics are viewed as the effects of selection
  rather than the causes of behavior. . . . The causes of behavior
  are not within the learner, except in the technical sense: The
  learner is the cumulative product of the selecting effects of past
  environments. . . [Donahoe & Palmer, 1994, p. 69]

just as wrong as the counterclaim that the past consequences of behavior
have nothing to do with the organism's future behavior. It is clear to me
that organisms are intentional and will work to change their environments as
necessary (if possible!) to produce what they want to perceive. And it is
equally clear to me that the organism is highly sensitive to its
environment-as-perceived, and will be altered by its experience with that
environment in ways that can be predicted from a knowledge of the
contingencies and of the organism's likes and dislikes (which can be assessed).

In closing, I'm sorry if my own intellectual history has resulted in a view
of behavior that is not 100% compatible with your own and that this has
occasionally (or even often) resulted in our being in conflict over issues.
Despite these differences, I continue to view PCT and its philosophical
underpinnings as offering extremely important insights, both with respect to
behavior and to methodology, and continue to be grateful to have this
opportunity to interact so extensively with you. I have not intended these
interactions to be destructive of PCT, but rather to provide some avenue
whereby these differences might be aired, and perhaps even resolved. I
continue to believe in the maxim that it is better to debate an issue
without settling it, than to settle an issue without debating it.

Regards,

Bruce A.

···

from my perspective (having been exposed to PCT), this is sheer nonsense,

[From Bruce Gregory (991116.1802 EST)]

Rick Marken (991116.1430)

> What does "choose" [mean] in the HPCT model?

Setting a reference for a particular state of a perception.

How did the child get to the RTC room if the child did not set a
reference for perceiving him or her self in the RTC room? (Assuming the
child was not picked up and carried to the room.)

Bruce Gregory

from Phil Runkel on 16 Nov 99:

[From Bruce Abbott, too damned early (2:25 a.m.) on 16 Nov 99]

>From Phil Runkel on 14 Nov 99

>writing about punishment and submission:

>I remember a professor at my graduate school who was an expert in learning
>theory (S-R), and who every now and then would tell a story about an
>experiment that went wrong....

I'm curious about this experiment, Phil. Who supposedly conducted it?
About when would it have been done? What was it about the experiment that
was supposed to have gone wrong?

Thanks for the interesting details about such experiments. -- especially
since you took time to write them out at a wee hour of the morning! That
lecture must have been given some time in 1952 at the Univ of Mich in Ann
Arbor. I was reconstructing it from memory, and you know how memories
are. The only detail in which I have full confidence is that the
professor (Edward E. Walker) told it as an example of how sometimes the
behavior of subjects seem not to conform to theory. Chances are your
guesses about how the experiment might have been conducted are closer to
fact than my memory.

···

On Tue, 16 Nov 1999, Bruce Abbot wrote:

[From Bill Powers (991117.0200 MDT)]

Bruce Abbott (991116.1720 EST)--

Well I haven't read Ed's book and have had only the descriptions offered on
CSGnet to go on. I'm glad that from your point of view, what actually goes
on is quite like my description.

Since my observations concern differences between what Ed Ford says in his
book and what is actually done in RTP schools, it seems to me that you
might need to read his book to evaluate what I say.

... If I pull the bottom
can from a stack of soup cans and the cans all tumble down, would you say
that I am the cause of the removal of the first can but that the stock clerk
who arranged the stack is the cause of the rest of the cans crashing down?

I would say you are the cause of the removal of the first can, and that the
tumbling of the remainder was caused by that removal, although it was
probably not your intention -- your "choice" -- to cause the rest to tumble.

The stock clerk, of course, is the cause of setting up a stack of cans in
such a way that if a bottom can is removed, the stack will fall. The clerk
at least shares any responsibility.

That is not, however, sufficiently like the case we're describing. When the
stock clerk has left the scene, the physical nature of the stack determines
what will ensue when a bottom can is removed; the fall of the stack is
physically caused by the can removal. But when we're talking about a social
rule the enforcement of which requires the active participation of the
adult, the situation is entirely different. A proper parallel would be for
the stock clerk to say, "If you remove this particular can, I will knock
the stack down. And because you know that, if you remove that can it will
be your choice if the stack falls down." This is just like saying "I am
making a rule that if you disrupt a second time after having been
cautioned, I will send you to the RTC. So if you disrupt a second time, it
will have been your choice to go to the RTC." That conclusion is unwarranted.

I'd say that the clerk set up the _conditions_ such that my removing the
bottom would have that consequence, but as to them actually crashing down,
that's _my_ doing. Similarly, the adult arranges the consequences for
misbehavior of the child and explains those consequences to the child, but
it is the child's actions that bring about those consequences, and in that
specific sense the child is responsible for their occurrence.

The parallel is flawed because the adult not only "arranges" the
consequences, but acts to make sure they occur. It is perfectly clear, in
that situation, that if it were not for the intentional actions of the
adult, those consequences would not be mandatory. They are artificial
consequences. If the child disrupts and chooses NOT to go to the RTC, it is
the adult who sees to it that the child ends up in the RTC anyway. That is
why it is a sham for the adult to claim that the child really has a choice.
If you have a choice you must be able to carry it out.

I believe that being dishonest with children is an effective way to lose
their love and respect. The subject of social rules -- who makes them and
how they are enforced -- is a very delicate one; it can easily be
mishandled. I think it's possible to introduce rules and rule enforcement
without taking the implacable view that Ed Ford takes, which is that
obeying the rules -- any rules, made by any adult -- is non-negotiable and
will be enforced by any means necessary. That approach may be effective in
suppressing dissent, but it does not teach children to deal with rules
effectively -- especially when _they_ become the adults.

O.K., this is close to what I had in mind.

Right, but it is not what Ed says in his book. I think you have to read the
book.

The idea that these contingencies are not the reason for the success of

RTP,

and that some hidden element, provided in some mysterious way by trained
PCTers, strikes me as incredible.

I guess you really don't understand what the "hidden element" is.

I understand what you _think_ the "hidden element" is.

Of course you do: it is abandoning the desire to control the child's
behavior by force, and starting to negotiate instead of bully the child.
Read Chapter 17 again. I recognize that you can control a person's behavior
by getting control of something the person needs, taking it away from the
person and then giving it back only if the person does what you want. If
you know that a child wants to be with his or her friends, you can use that
knowledge to control the child by taking the child away from the friends.
First you cause distress; then you kindly offer to remove the distress if
the child will obey you. But you can't pretend that you never did the first
part of the process; even if you deny it to yourself, the child you did it
to knows what you did.

A fancy name like "contingency" or "reinforcer" doesn't change what is
done. You have to be enough stronger than the other person, or smarter or
older, to get control of and withhold what the person needs in the first
place, so you can give it as a means of controlling the person. And you
constantly have to be vigilant and keep the person from getting back
control of the needed thing. This is the old way of orqanizing schools, by
using rewards and punishments to force a student to obey the rules.

You believe that this is the natural, normal, and technically effective way
to deal with children. You admire the RTP approach because you see it
making the contingencies plain and being consistent about maintaining them.
According to your beliefs, this should lead to effective control of the
children's behavior. Since you believe that control of their behavior is
what is desired, you assume that this management of contingencies accounts
for the success of the RTP program. But all you're telling me is that your
faith in reward and punishment is such that you can't believe that RTP does
not succeed because of them. In a similar way, you tell me that you can't
believe that a properly-conducted behavior-mod approach could fail. Yet if
you didn't believe that controlling children's behavior is a good thing to
do, you could not sustain any of those beliefs.

None of the elements of RTP that I have outlined above _should be_
incompatible with PCT (although as characterized in this forum it is always
depicted as incompatible).

What is incompatible is using force and the threat of force to control the
behavior of children. If you try to use rewards and punishments to control
the behavior of another human being of any age, conflict is inevitable. The
problem in schools is not insufficient conflict, but too much conflict
between children and adults. What you see as effective about Ed's program
is precisely what I see as a source of conflict rather than a cure for it.

From my,
probably unique, perspective I can see how certain principles from behavior
analysis and others from control theory can be unified into a coherent
theory of behavior with considerable power. I know why you believe that
these principles are incompatible and I think I understand why this belief
is incorrect. Unfortunately, I haven't had much success in convincing you
of this.

You haven't tried. All you have done is tell me that your interpretation
makes sense to you. You have never countered my argument that reward and
punishment rely fundamentally on the possession and, if necessary,
application of superior force.

It is all too easy for you to simply explain this conflict away by
assuming that I am a victim of my own past and, like the "old school" of
Kuhnian lore, will simply have to retire or pass away to make way for the

new.

If that were my only objection you would be right. But none of my
objections to the behavior-mod approach (which simply assumes the right of
one person to control another's behavior) refers to you or your past. You
seem to think that by showing that the behavior-mod approach can actually
modify behavior, you have shown that this is a good thing to do. I say it
is a very bad way to do things; children, like anyone else, need to be able
to vary their behavior freely to achieve what they want. If there are
consequences of that behavior -- real, not made-up consequences -- that the
child doesn't like, the child has to be free to try other behaviors that
will not only fix what the child doesn't like, but also continue to
maintain the kinds of experiences the child does like. An adult who
prescribes the behavior of the child and then brings to bear all the
influences he can find to make the child behave that way is not helping the
child become a skillful adult.

What isn't readily apparent from my interactions on CSGnet is that I am even
more troubled by many of the standard assumptions/conclusions of many EABers
in particular and research psychologists in general. I agree with you that
the whole damned field is a sorry mess, and is unlikely to improve any time
soon.

Yes, and I liked your example. But how do you know that what you call a
"unification" of PCT and other principles is not simply a way to avoid
giving up that last bit of belief in the whole scheme of behaviorism?

From my perspective (having been exposed to PCT), this is sheer nonsense,

just as wrong as the counterclaim that the past consequences of behavior
have nothing to do with the organism's future behavior. It is clear to me
that organisms are intentional and will work to change their environments as
necessary (if possible!) to produce what they want to perceive. And it is
equally clear to me that the organism is highly sensitive to its
environment-as-perceived, and will be altered by its experience with that
environment in ways that can be predicted from a knowledge of the
contingencies and of the organism's likes and dislikes (which can be

assessed).

Of course, but why do you think that last statement is not already part of
the scheme of PCT? "Contingencies" are simply the effects our actions have,
through the environment, on our perceptions. What matters is not only what
those effects are, but what we want them to be -- our reference signals. To
know our "likes and dislikes" is to have deduced what perceptions we are
controlling and what our reference levels for them are. And to understand
that, one has to realize that reference signals, likes and dislikes, are
not the permanent things that such terms suggest, but highly variable
reference settings, which vary so as to keep still higher-level perceptions
in the states we prefer.

The final break with behaviorism can come only with the realization that
"behavior", in the sense of what we see other organisms doing, is not what
is important. Despite the basic assumption of reinforcement theory, which
is that the reinforcement draws forth "the" behavior that produces it,
there is no one action that will normally produce a given result. Behavior
may well have to change in order to produce the same reinforcement, in a
world that is not deliberately set up to avoid that ambiguity. Thus there
is nothing to reinforce, and reinforcement theory cannot explain what we
observe. In the laboratory, where repeating a reinforcement can be done
only by repeating the behavior that produced it, an illusion of causality
is created. But in a natural environment where nothing is protected against
disturbances, that illusion is quickly shattered when we see _different_
behaviors producing _the same_ reinforcement. And not accidentally
different behaviors: the differences are precisely the ones required, given
environmental circumstances, to see to it that the same result repeats.

In the PCT view it is not environmental events that cause changes in the
organism, but mechanisms in the organism that are specifically organized to
create change, and without which external events would have no effects on
the organism's behavior. The problem I see continuing in your approach,
despite your clear grasp of most PCT principles, is that you are still
willing to accept an _apparent_ cause as the _real_ cause. So if a stimulus
occurs and there is a response to it, you do not follow up by asking _what
is the mechanism_? You just take it at face value: the stimulus must have
had some effect that made a response appropriate to the stimulus occur.

I continue to believe in the maxim that it is better to debate an issue
without settling it, than to settle an issue without debating it.

I think we have satisfied that requirement several times over. We're down
to matters of faith now. When your only argument is "I just can't believe
...", you have run out of arguments. It is only belief that stands in the
way. So belief is what has to go.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bill Powers (991116.0407 MDT)]

Bruce Gregory (991116.1802 EST)--

How did the child get to the RTC room if the child did not set a
reference for perceiving him or her self in the RTC room? (Assuming the
child was not picked up and carried to the room.)

If necessary, the child _is_ picked up and carried to the room. I asked Ed,
and that is what he said. The child has no say about whether or not he or
she will go to the RTC, once the second disruption has occurred. Of course
Ed claims that children almost never have to be physically forced to go to
the RTC. I could understand that; given only the choice between walking and
being dragged or carried, I would pick walking. At a higher level, of
course, I may remain dissatisfied with being in that situation at all, but
there is nothing I can do about it at that level.

Later on, children come to value their time in the RTC and even volunteer
to go there to get their heads straight. That shows that something is being
done that offsets the unpleasantness of being forced to leave the class.

Best,

Bill P.

[From Bruce Gregory (991117.0640 EST)]

Bill Powers (991116.0407 MDT)

Bruce Gregory (991116.1802 EST)--

>How did the child get to the RTC room if the child did not set a
>reference for perceiving him or her self in the RTC room? (Assuming the
>child was not picked up and carried to the room.)

If necessary, the child _is_ picked up and carried to the room. I
asked Ed,
and that is what he said. The child has no say about whether or not he or
she will go to the RTC, once the second disruption has occurred. Of course
Ed claims that children almost never have to be physically forced to go to
the RTC. I could understand that; given only the choice between
walking and
being dragged or carried, I would pick walking. At a higher level, of
course, I may remain dissatisfied with being in that situation at all, but
there is nothing I can do about it at that level.

Later on, children come to value their time in the RTC and even volunteer
to go there to get their heads straight. That shows that
something is being
done that offsets the unpleasantness of being forced to leave the class.

I appreciate your response, but it did not answer my question. If the child
walks to the RTC room, how did it get there with setting a reference level
for being there? If the child sets a reference level for being in the RTC,
why is it "dishonest" to say that the child chose to go to the RTC room, if
Rick is correct and choosing in HPCT means setting a reference level? I'm
quite mystified at this point.

Bruce Gregory

In a message dated 11/17/99 6:59:32 AM, ssaunde@IBM.NET writes:

Sometimes it is necessary to to have a coercive elements in
a program, at least within our current understanding; refusing to admit
that
will not make the program no-coercixe, but will make the description
dishonest and may make it harder to make efforts to reduce the degree of
coercion involved.

Samuel:

Nice to hear from you. I too have held back responding in this thread. The
water has passed over the dam long ago with detrimental results among PCTers.

Life can create odd bed fellows at times. On this issue, I too am in bed
with Rick. And, that is mutually disturbing I suspect. :sunglasses:

RTP is designed to be fundamentally coercive to disruptive students in any
normal understanding of the word, as well as the proposed PCT concept
promoted by Rick and Bill. And, it has to be! Further, school
administrators have no problem accepting this. It is their modus operandi.

The laws of the land force public school systems to be designed by its
officials to be fundamentally coercive. This in turn coerces RTP to comply
with its rules and coerce disruptive kids. Kids have to attend school
whether they want to or not, and whether they are learning anything or not.
To me, it seems stupid for society and there are alternatives, but that is
the accepted law of the land.

To avoid the stigma of openly admitting RTP is a fundamentally different,
potentially superior, but still a coercive, school discipline system by
saying it gives students a choice to behave responsibly falls into what is
often called "saleman's puff." It has an element of truth, but does not
convey the whole picture. Nor is voluntarily revealing the whole truth
required by law for all products.

I don't really understand why the RTP advocates can't relent and change the
puffy description of RTP along the lines suggested by Bill Powers. Nor do I
understand why Rick and Bill have to keep pounding away beating this dead
horse on one of the better applications of PCT around. If it is that
important and antithetical to PCT, shouldn't Bill ask Ed Ford to cease and
desist referencing PCT in RTP?

Your point above strikes me as rational and responsible. I fail to
understand what is so adverse about adults placed in authority over children
exercising that authority over disruptive individuals for the good of the
group. It is what I would do with my disruptive child and I have no problem
authorizing my child's teacher or school administrator acting similarly for
me. RTP even seems to have a reasonable rationale to support its intention
to be in the long term interest of the disrupter.

I guess I am pleading for Ed and Bill to reach a mutually acceptable
accommodation and bury the hatchet and put this issue to rest. Isn't RTP
intended to help students learn to control their own behavior responsibly as
a superior alternative to having teachers and administrators _continue_ to
use their duly accepted authority to control the behavior of the students?

If Ed and Bill can't accommodate one another, the potential for using PCT as
a means to solve behavioral problems is itself constrained by its biggest
advocates. That is sad.

[From Bruce Gregory (991117.0944 EST)]

I have been straining not to respond to your posts in this
thread.

Self restraint is not always easy to exercise.

This is
just to convoluted and unreasonable to let pass. Rick never
said he was not
responsible for speeding. What he said, and what anyone
without an ax to
grind could see,

Could you share with us exactly what axes you are referring to and who
is grinding them?

is that he did not choose to receive a
ticket, go to court,
pay a fine, perhaps pay an increased insurance premium, and
so on.

By which you mean, I assume, that he was not controlling for these
outcomes. Or did you have something else in mind? What, in your view
_was_ Rick controlling for? How might we test this conjecture?

Just so,
the child has chosen to do what he has done, but not
necessarily to leave
the classroom.

Ditto.

Sometimes it is necessary to have a
coercive elements in
a program, at least within our current understanding;
refusing to admit that
will not make the program no-coercive, but will make the description
dishonest and may make it harder to make efforts to reduce
the degree of
coercion involved.

An inspiring call for honesty. How could anyone disagree? Do you think
that I or anyone else is championing dishonesty? If so, do you have any
evidence to support this remarkable conjecture?

Samuel Spence Saunders, Ph.D.

Good for you! It's nice to see someone who is proud of his
accomplishments.

Bruce Gregory, S.F.G.

p.s. If you look back on posts to the net you will discover how to put a
proper heading on your messages. I have no axe to grind about this, just
trying to be helpful.