So when the sheep observes the alteration in the distance between them caused by the dog’s movement, there will come a point where the management of that distance takes priority over the management of the perception of hunger or achieving contact with some tasty looking grass. Â MOL is appropriate when the switch keeps alternating back and forth because priority cannot be established in any satisfactory manner for any specified length of time or circumstance. Â There might be such a distance (like the ass between two bales of hay who starves to death) but the dog would have to stand still at the distance just as the grass stands still. Â Otherwise there does not seem to be any conflict, just a change in priority. Â Might it be appropriate to talk about influencing the priority of another’s reference conditions rather than talking about influencing their behavior? Â Boris has one video which shows a sheep head butting a dog who is clearing not harming the sheep. Â They appear to be playing. Â The sheep turns toward the dog as it approaches and put its head down, the dog contacts the head and slides to one side, but does not grab anything while the sheep spins orient its head toward the dog and then they separate and do the whole thing over again. Â This might be an example of co-reorganization (protocols?) of these two particular animals and their history of interaction with each other.
It seems to me that if I want to get you to do something in particular, I will have to be able to influence what reference condition currently has priority in your hierarchy. Â This means that I must have some conception of your hierarchy, its contents, how they are prioritized, and what changes in perception influence that process prioritization. Being a member of a group and sharing a language makes this at least possible some of the time. Â If I see my spouse going toward the kitchen and say “can you bring me a beer?” and she says, “sure”. Â There is no other observable change in her behavior. Â Moments later, she sets a beer down next to me and I say, “thanks” as she walks back to a chair in the living room. Â Have I controlled her behavior or did I simply give her an opportunity to change the priority of some reference condition that she already had built into her hierarchy? Â When I share information about myself, am I disturbing her? Â She could have said, “No, I’m on my way to Jan’s” and I would know that she did not change her priorities and I would know what I needed to do if I wanted a beer. Â The fact that she told me where she was going, might have been a change in her priorities, how would anyone other than her know if that was the case? Â Each of us has some awareness of the sequences of reference conditions that we are engaged in controlling. Â
The discussion of controlling our perception of the behavior of others has led to some serious thinking (good old armchair) about what kind of model a self-conscious control system might need to have about another self-conscious control system in order in order to succeed at intentionally controlling some variables together. Â
Thanks to one and all - I have also some ideas how to use youtube as part of a research process,
Thanks, Boris
bob
···
On Fri, Sep 12, 2014 at 12:40 PM, Richard Marken rsmarken@gmail.com wrote:
[From Rick Marken (2014.09.12.1041)]
On 2014/09/12 12:28 PM, Bob Hintz
wrote:
bob hintz - 2014.09.12
I think Boris has collected some nice video references
here. Â He also raises another issue. Â When a sheep is eating
(controlling for internal perceptions of nutrition by chomping
clumps of grass, chewing and swallowing) its observable
behavior is different than when it is controlling the distance
between itself and the dog. Â
Martin Taylor (2014.09.12.12.46)
MT: You are talking about conflict between different control systems.
RM: Excellent post Martin!!
BestÂ
Rick
The conflict occurs when two control systems want to set one
perceptual variable (location on the field) to two different places.
The “eating” set of control systems wants to be where the grass is
lush, while the “safety” set of control systems wants to be away
from the dog. How conflicts get resolved is a generic question in
PCT with probably several different answers. Indeed, that’s what MOL
is about.From the outside, conflict resolution looks like choice or decision,
and maybe that’s actually what happens. Maybe one control system
turns its gain down to zero and lets the other one win. Maybe some
switch disconnects one and allows the other to control. Maybe they
both keep providing output but there’s a system nonlinearity
somewhere that allows one of them to dominate. There are several
possibilities. In any particular case, I suppose that it would be
possible to model the effects of different possible ways a conflict
is resolved. Kent McClelland would be a good one to ask about this.
But we can’t tell in the case of the sheep.If you were out in the jungle picking berries to stave off hunger
and you thought you heard a tiger, would you imagine you would keep
on picking berries? If not, what perceptions would you imagine
yourself to now be controlling that you were not controlling before
you thought you heard the tiger? And why?Martin
–
Richard S. Marken, Ph.D.
Author of  Doing Research on Purpose.Â
Now available from Amazon or Barnes & Noble
On Thu, Sep 11, 2014 at 10:31 AM, Boris
Hartman boris.hartman@masicom.net
wrote:
Hi Rick,
Â
RM: Exactly, the dog controls the
behavior of the sheep by disturbing a variable that
the sheep control by grouping themselves closer
together. Boris disagrees and says that the sheep
are not being controlled by the dog, which is
demonstrably wrong. Without the dog there, the gaps
between the sheep would on average be quite wide.
Â
Â
HB
:
First
of all nobody can control any behavior. Neither dog
or sheep. Both control their own perception.
Â
So
if I see right your »attack on me« that I’m wrong,
you are trying to say that dog and sheep are
controlling for the same perception : the gap
between sheep and so it seems to you that dog
controls the behavior of sheep. And that’s by your
oppinion proof that sheeps are controlled by dog. Or
in other words : because sheeps behave as dog wants,
sheeps are controlled. Did I missed something ?
Â
The
problem here is that sheep could control the
perception of the gap between sheep, for safety as
you said. But when you say safety what does it mean.
If we say just control for safety we don’t know what
is really controlled. I asssume that safety could be
higher order perception, composed of at least two
lower level controlled perceptions : distance
between ship and distance between dog and sheep.
Both controlled perceptions are contributing to
safety, specialy the last one.
Â
But
sheep do control at least one more life-important
perception : eating grass. When they control such a
perception they spread on great teritory seeking for
better grass, not seeking for control of gap between
them. That’s what owners of sheep wants. So owner
train a dog to group sheep so not to be spread
arround.
Â
Sheeps
are not controlling only for the gap between sheep,
they control for their life-important perception.
The owner of course also control that sheep could
eat best grass. Dog and people who trained dog, do
control for sheep being togetheras as much as
possible to eat grass, but also not to lose any of
sheep.
Â
So
I think you are right that dog control for »the gap
between sheep« as that’s what owner wants. But I
think you are not right that dog controls the
behavior of sheep by controlling the gap among them.
 Sheep can control for different perception among
which is also perception of grouping together for
safety. But behavior of sheep is not determined with
presence of the dog, but depends from sheep’s
internal control by which relevant behavior (output)
for the sheep’s control of perception is
established. Â
Â
Sheep
beside very important control of eating grass,
control also perception for the distance to the
predator (in our case it’s dog). Â It’s probably some
inborn survival behavior. So sheep control for the
perception of distance to dog. Here is video, which
show how group of sheeps are moving in accordance
with distance to the dog. When dogs are at safe
diastance (probably low »error« in sheep control)
sheeps are not moving. When distance minimize sheep
move (run) away from dog. But the distance is
varying in accordance to control of sheep and dog.
When sheep control differently – run away from
group, than we can see that sheep in control of
their perception. Â
Â
Â
So
we can conclude that there are many »survivial
behaviors« or sheep can control for different
perceptions. One of them and very important is : the
gap between dog (predator) and sheep. With output
sheep will control perception of being enough far
from dog. We can say that sheep controls the
distance to the dog (predator) and varying distance
will in some proportion (not linear) cause »errors«
in control. The closer dog is, more »error« and more
distance to the dog is produced, less »error« no
activity or perception of eating grass is
controlled.
Dog's
controlled perception is : the more the sheep are
together – less »error«, the more theey are appart –
more »error«. So again varying distance, varying
»error« of dog control. Also seen in video when one
sheep ran away from group. Dogs ran after it.
Â
So
both : dog and sheep are controllig what they are
supposed to control.
Â
Now
Rick you can make simulation of both LCS each
controling for own perception – varying percepttion
of distance. We have only to establish, how these
diferent controls with different goals are
coordinated. I would say that dog run in different
directions trying to change the distance to sheep so
to move sheep in wanted direction.
Â
In
this way sheep is stil controlling for distance and
less »error« in the direction of group of other
sheep mean that is more possibility for sheep to
move to the group. So in this case sheep is tending
to encrease the gap to the dog and dog somehow
enable that. But this is not always the case.
Â
So
I concluded that dog behavior is not always
implaying sheep behavior to increase distance to the
dog only by running away. It can be also different.
In next video you can see that sheeps choose another
behavior, which has something to do with the dog,
but in opposite direction. Instead of increasing the
gap to the dog, with running away, they choose the
control of perception of moving the dog away. So
they attack dog. Â
Â
Â
Your
term Rick about controling other living being
somehow sounds to me as S-R logic. Dog behavior
(stimulus, disturbance) to sheep perceptual input,
and then directly to sheep behavior is somehow
determined sheep behavior by it’s input
(environment). It’s denying Bill’s aymetry of
control : LCS can control environment, and
environment can’t control LCS.
Â
By
your control of behavior of others can happen in the
opposite  way.  So it sounds like absolutely
determined behavior by environment : sheep input
(dogs behavior) - sheep output (induced behavior by
dog behavior). Nothing in between. No process inside
»controlled« LCS counts, no references, no
reorganization, just stream from input to output
(control of others).
Â
LCS
are already controlling, so nobody can overtake that
control. Sheep all the time control their
perception. Â Dogs all the time control their
percpetion.
Â
I
didn’t find any example to show how sheep can attack
alone sheep dog, not just ran away form the dog, but
I found this video, which shows how sheep attacked
wolf, when he comes to close.
Â
If
we think that sheep are inocent little animals
harmly eating grass, we can made a hudge mistake :
here is video which show how nasty can be sheep
attack.
Â
Maybe
this video will help to see, how sheep control the
distance to dog (predator) :
Â
And
maybe one more video which shows that dog is not
controlling the behavior of the ram.
Â
And
maybe the last video that shows that perceptual
control is choosen in the ram not in environment and
can be very unpredictable and dangerous.
Â
Â
All
in all I think that there is enough proof that dogs
are not controlling behavior of the sheep, but sheep
control it’s own perception that it chooses  and dog
control it’s perception that it chooses. But neither
of them can control behavior. Nor own, neither
others. As far as I understand there is no such a
thing in PCT. Â
Â
Best,
Â
Boris
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
Â
From:
csgnet-request@lists.illinois.edu
[mailto:csgnet-request@lists.illinois.edu ]
On Behalf Of Richard Marken
Sent: Tuesday, September 09, 2014 2:45 AM
To: csgnet@lists.illinois.edu
Subject: Re: Sheepdog and flock behavior
Â
[From Rick Marken
(2014.09.08.1545)]
Â
Kent McClelland
(2014.09.07.2050)
Â
KM: I see that my name has
come up in this exchange, so I’ll see if I can
say anything to help move it along. As I look
at what you’ve written, I don’t see much in
either person’s position to disagree with, but
you seem to be at an impasse. The difficulty
seems to be semantic, revolving around what it
means to control another person’s behavior,
which Rick says can be done and Boris says
can’t. In my view, you’re both partly right.
Â
RM: I think it's more
than semantic. I think the difficulty turns
on knowing what control is, in fact, not
in theory. Once you know what control is
then there is no controversy at all:
behavior can be controlled. That’s what we
are seeing with the sheepdogs (the dogs
controlling the gaps between the sheep) and
with the E and S in the rubber band demo (E
controlling the finger position of S). A
variable (the gap, the finger position) is
being kept in a pre-selected state (0 gap,
finger on target dot), protected from
disturbance (autonomously produced changes
in the closeness of the sheep to one
another, the closeness of the finger to the
target dot) by varying actions appropriately
(moving towards or away from the sheep,
increasing or reducing the pull on the
rubber band) .
Â
KM: The problem, as I see
it, is that a person’s behavior (or that of
any living control system with hierarchical
control of perceptions) is never just one
thing. A person controls lots of different
perceptions simultaneously, at different
perceptual levels. And when a person
observes another person’s physical actions,
the observer can see “behaviors” at a lot of
different perceptual levels.
Â
RM: Yes, but this is true
of all of our experience, not just our
experience of other people’s behavior. We
control perceptual variables of many
different types (hypothetically 11 different
types of perceptual variable). I don’t see
what this has to do with whether or not
people can control other people’s behavior.
Â
KM:
Because a person controls lots of
different things at once, under the right
circumstances another person can control
SOME of these behaviors (as the controller
perceives them), but not ALL of them, at
least not all of them simultaneously. The
trick in controlling a particular behavior
by another person (call it behavior A) is
to get the person to focus on controlling
behavior B, and then to remove all the
other ways for the person to keep
controlling behavior B except by doing
behavior A.
Â
RM: Yes, this is all I
claimed was true: people can control the
behavior of other people. Of course, they
can only control some of these behaviors
– the one’s that correct for disturbances
to the variable the controllee is
controlling. This is why I gave the example
of controlling the position of S’s finger in
the rubber band demo. Since S must vary the
position of the finger in order to
compensate for E- produced disturbances to
the position of the knot, Â the variable S is
controlling, E can control S’s finger
position by disturbing the position of the
knot. S’s finger position is the only aspect
of S’s behavior that E can control in this
situation. But that aspect of S’s behavior
can certainly be controlled.
KM: That's the classic pattern for
manipulation of a person’s behavior.
Â
RM: Right! This is how
you can manipulate (control) another
 person’s behavior.Â
Â
KM: The pattern also
applies to the dog and sheep example.
Â
RM: Exactly, the dog
controls the behavior of the sheep by
disturbing a variable that the sheep control
by grouping themselves closer together.
Boris disagrees and says that the sheep are
not being controlled by the dog, which is
demonstrably wrong. Without the dog there,
the gaps between the sheep would on average
be quite wide.
Â
KM: Thus, the control of
one person’s behavior by another person can
and does happen
Â
RM: Â My point exactly. Â
Â
> RM: One example: When
I give a cashier $10 for a $5 item I am
controlling for the cashier giving me $5
change. The cashier is also controlling for me
paying $5 for the item. Typically, we both get
the behaviors from each other than we want: a
nice example of mutual control, and no one
gets hurt (or oppressed). This kind of agreed
on mutual control is the basis of
civilization.KM: Martin Taylor, in the chapter he's
writing for the LCS IV book edited by Warren
Mansell (a preliminary draft of which I’ve
been lucky enough to see), calls this kind
of exchange transaction a “protocol,”
Â
RM: I looked at Martin's
reply and what he describes as a “protocol” is
not the same as the mutual controlling that
occurs in the customer/cashier interaction.Â
Â
KM: and, if I understand
his concept correctly, protocols provide a way
for two people acting together to control two
different perceptions. The side-effects of one
person’s behavior in controlling his or her
own perception allow the other person to
control a different perception (and
vice-versa). In your example, the cashier
controls the perception of completing a sale
by getting your money and giving you the item
and $5 change, while you control the
perception of buying the item by handing over
the money and getting the item and change
back.
Â
RM: The difference
between the customer/cashier interaction and
the interaction between two control systems
described by Martin is that there is no
control of one control system by another in
the situation Martin describes. In the
customer/cashier situation, successful
control by each control system requires
successful control of  each control system’s
behavior by the other control system. In
Martin’s “protocol”, shown below, Alan’s
ability to control PA does not depend on
controlling Beth’s behavior and vice versa.
 The actions Alan uses to control PA are a
disturbance to PB which Beth will oppose
along with any other disturbances to PB, and
vice versa. Â But Alan’s ability to control
PA does not depend on his controlling Beth’s
behavior. INdeed, Alan can control PA just
fine whether Beth is controlling PB or not.Â
Â
Â
This is quite different
from the customer/cashier situation. The
customer is controlling for paying the exact
cost for the product; the cashier is
controlling for collecting the exact payment.
If the product costs $5 and the customer hands
$10 to the cashier, the customer will achieve
the “pay the exact cost” goal only if the
cashier returns the exact change. So the
customer is controlling for the cashier
returning $5. Â The cashier is also controlling
for collecting the cost of the customer’s item
and so will allow the customer to leave with
the product only after payment has been
received. If the cashier were not controlling
for getting only the exact amount for the
product the customer would not successfully
control for getting the correct change
behavior from the cashier; if the customer
were not controlling for paying for the
product the cashier would not successfully
control for getting paid by the customer.Â
Â
KM: I don't think I
would describe this exchange situation as
control of another person’s behavior
Â
RM: Apparently Bob
Hintz doesn’t think so either. Â But,
again, I think it can be easily
demonstrated that both the customer and
cashier are, in fact , controlling
each other’s behavior by introducing
disturbances to the hypothetical behavior
variables that are being controlled. For
example, have the cashier give the
customer $4 rather $5 dollars in change –
a disturbance to the customer’s perception
of the cashier returning the correct
change. I think you will see the customer
take action – like arguing with the
cashier – to bring the cashier’s behavior
to the desired state: handing over the $5
change. Similarly, have the customer hand
the cashier $4 rather than $5. I think you
will see the cashier take action – like
calling over the manager – to bring the
customer’s behavior to the desired state:
pay for the product. So the customer is
controlling for the “returning correct
change” behavior of the cashier and the
cashier is controlling for the “paying for
the product” behavior of the customer.Â
Â
KM: unless you were
buying the item from someone who had a
monopoly, and the only way for you to get
the item (behavior B) would be to pay the
asking price (behavior A). Even then, you
could refuse to buy the item or just get
something else, unless the item were
something you couldn’t live without.
Â
RM: I hope my little
explanation shows that this is not
necessary. The customer and cashier are
controlling each other’s behavior but it
doesn’t look like they are controlling
each other’s behavior (and they certainly
don’t feel like they are controlling each
other) until one or the other doesn’t
behave as desired. Â This is the way it is
with all our controlling, though, isn’t
it? We don’t feel like we are controlling
when we walk down the street or talk on
the phone or swim in the lake – that is,
we don’t notice our controlling until we
start to lose it .Skillful control does’t
feel like anything special; it just feels
like we are doing things. Â And
this is true of skillful controlling of
our own limbs, of the physical
consequences of limb movements (like
walking and swimming) and interpersonal
consequences of these limb movements (like
getting change from a cashier). Â
Â
RM: I think I
understand why people don’t want to
believe that they can be controlled and
why they do want to believe that they
never control other people. It fits with
our idea that we are “free” and “good”.
But I think it’s better to recognize when
we are controlling, especially when we are
controlling (and being controlled by)
other control systems. Understanding how
to recognize this is, I think, one of the
most important things to learn from PCT.
It’s only when you know that you are
controlling (and being controlled) that
you can adjust your own controlling to
reduce inter (and intra) personal conflict
and work to organize society in a way that
allows controllers to do their controlling
with the least amount of conflict and the
greatest amount of cooperation with other
controllers. Making believe that we can’t
be controlled or that we are not
controlled by and/or don’t control other
controllers is not the road to a better
world, I think.
Â
BestÂ
Â
Rick
Â
Â
Hope these thoughts help you to clarify
the questions you were discussing.
Best, Kent
On Sep 7, 2014, at 12:54 PM, Richard
Marken wrote:
> [From Rick Marken
(2014.09.07.1100)]
> > <boris.hartman@masicom.net >
wrote:
> > > BH : I don't think that dogs were
controlling gaps by »controlling sheeps
behavior«. Sheeps were controlling their
behavior on the bases of disturbances
dog produced to sheep perceptual
control.> > > RM: Yes, the sheep were controlling
a perception (I called it safety) to
which the approach of the dog was a
disturbance. The sheep compensated for
this disturbance by moving closer to
other sheep. This is the behavior that
the dog wanted to see (were controlling
for) because it closed the gaps that
were a disturbance to the perception the
dog was controlling. So the dog was able
to control the behavior of the sheep,
getting them to bunch closer together,
because the sheep were controlling for
safety by bunching together.> > RM : So any model of this behavior
would have to model the dogs’ “gap”
control system and the sheep’s safety
control system. Such a simulation would
show that control systems can both
control and be controlled.> > > > > BH : Well this is a good idea to
make simultaneous simulation. Did you
try it ?> > > RM: Not yet. > > > > BH: But this is the n-th time that
we are trying to solve the problem how
LCS can be “controlled”. In the book :
Making sense of behavior Bill talks
about “attempts of control” not
“control”…> > > > BH: Maybe Kent could explain what's
wrong with your position about »LCS can
be controlled".> > > RM: Yes, I think that's a good
idea, though I would be surprised if
Kent thought that there is something
wrong with my “position”. My position is
simply that people can clearly control
the behavior other people and their own
behavior can be controlled as well. This
is an observable fact that is explained
by PCT. I leave the explanation as an
exercise.> > RM : It can also be easily
demonstrated with humans using the
rubber band demo; the E in this
experiment can control the finger
position of the S once S has agreed to
control the position of the knot.> > > > BH : Yes. Watch your wording in
rubber band demo. “Once S has agreed” or
as Kent said “S chooses”. . So it’s
obviously that S agreed to be
controlled.> > > RM: Not quite. S has agreed to
control a particular perception (the
location of the knot relative to the
dot, in this case). S has not agreed to
be controlled; indeed, S is typically
unaware of being controlled after
agreeing to control that perception.> > HB : Aplying distrubance to a
»controlled variable« does not mean that
control is established. It seems that
Kent and I agree that disturbances are
aplyed to perceptual control and target
person chooses.> > > RM: I would be interested to hear
what Kent has to say about that. I would
be very surprised if he agreed with your
analysis.> > > RM : Nor does control theory show
that controlling organisms (particularly
humans) is necessarily a bad thing to
do.> > > > > BH : Now you are exaggerating Rick.
You can’t control organisms. I’d really
like to see how you are doing that in
everyday life ?> >
> RM: One example: When I
give a cashier $10 for a $5 item I am
controlling for the cashier giving me $5
change. The cashier is also controlling
for me paying $5 for the item. Typically,
we both get the behaviors from each other
than we want: a nice example of mutual
control, and no one gets hurt (or
oppressed). This kind of agreed on mutual
control is the basis of civilization.> >Â RM : What control
theory does show is that arbitrary
control, particularly of humans by other
humans, will almost certainly lead to
conflict. Arbitrary control is exerting
control without considering the fact
that living control systems are
controlling many variables at the same
time and when you arbitrarily decide to
have a person do something (by
disturbing a controlling variable) what
you have them do may conflict with other
things they are controlling.> > > > > HB : It makes some sense, but I
don’t understand what you meant by
»arbitrary control« ?> > > RM: It means controlling without
taking a persons wants and needs (the
references for the many different
perceptions that the person is
controlling for) into account. In
non-PCT terms, it is controlling another
person without respecting that person’s
humanity (and autonomy).> > BH: If you are thinking like this
one : »Controlle behavior match my
wanted perception of behvior and thus it
is »controlled« it’s wrong.> > > RM: That's exactly how I am
thinking. And I think you are wrong
about this being wrong.> > BH: You have PCT which helps you
understand what’s happening inside
organisms. Human control and behavior
are quite unpredictable, because the
references are formed inside organism,
where most of control is done.> > > RM: Once you have correctly
identified a controlled variable
behavior (the actions that protect that
variable from disturbance) can be
predicted with very high accuracy. See
the “Basic Control demo” at http://www.mindreadings.com/ControlDemo/BasicTrack.html
to see what I mean.> > BH: Just observable »facts« of
behavioral event are not prove that
people control each other. Although it’s
not excluded. The controller’s behavior
is just a disturbance to controlee
perceptual control. From what happens in
controlee comparator (error) will
probably decide whether controlee
behavior will resemble to something
controller wanted or not. But never
behavior of controlee will be just exact
»copy« of controller’s wanted behavior,
because controlee is in control.> > >Â RM: It may not be an "exact" copy
of what the controller wants, but it can
be very close (like within 1% of the
desired value).> > > > > RM: Anyway, this behavior --
managing flocks – is a very interesting
demonstration of controlling a
perception (of gaps between sheep) via
disturbance of a perception being
controlled by the control systems that
are being controlled.> > > > BH: This one makes some PCT sense.
J
> > > RM: Well, that's progress! > > Best > > Rick > > > > > But as usual I'm living space for
not understanding something right. And
as always, sorry for my language.> > > > Best, > > > > Boris > > > > > > From: csgnet-request@lists.illinois.edu [mailto:csgnet-request@lists.illinois.edu ]
On Behalf Of Richard Marken
> Sent: Sunday, August 31, 2014 3:23
AM
> To: csgnet@lists.illinois.edu > Subject: Re: Sheepdog and flock
behavior
> > > > [From Rick Marken
(2014.08.30.1820)]
> > > > [From Bruce Abbott (2014.08.30.0820
EDT)]
> > > > Researchers have investigated how
sheepdogs manage their flocks by fitting
both the dogs and the sheep with highly
accurate GPS devices, allowing the
researchers to track their movements.Â
The research is presented in a BBC
article at http://www.bbc.com/news/science-environment-28936251
.> > > > RM: Great find, Bruce! There are
two things that make this report
particularly interesting to me. The
first is the quote by Andrew King, which
is a great description of the PCT
approach to research. To paraphrase
King: in order to understand the
behavior of organisms you have to try to
look at their behavior from the point of
view of the organism (behaving system)
Itself. I make this same point in the
chapter on “Looking at Behavior through
Control Theory Glasses” in “Doing
Research on Purpose” (why hasn’t that
become a best seller yet?). I do it in
the section on trying to understand the
apparent “fixed action pattern” of the
greylag goose. The goose is seen to
continue to make the movements that
would pull an egg back into its nest
even when the egg is no longer present.
Looking at an organism’s behavior from
the organism’s perspective helps you
come up with good ideas about what
perceptual variables the organism is
controlling (the first step in the Test
for the Controlled Variable). By looking
at the goose’s egg rolling behavior from
the goose’s perspective I was able to
come up with the hypothesis that the
goose is trying to control the pressure
of the egg against the back of its bill
and when the egg is removed the
continued efforts to move the
non-existent egg into the nest (the
apparent fixed action pattern) is just
the efforts of the pressure control
system to restore the pressure of the
egg against the back of the bill. By
looking at the sheepdogs herding
behavior from the dogs’ perspective King
came up with the reasonable hypothesis
that the dogs were controlling their
perception of the gaps between patches
of white (the sheep), trying to keep
those gaps at zero.> > > > RM: The other thing that's
interesting about this report is that
the dogs were clearly controlling their
perception of the gaps by controlling
the behavior of the sheep. And they did
this by becoming a disturbance to a
perception that the sheep control by
getting closer to other sheep: the
perception of safety. So any model of
this behavior would have to model the
dogs’ “gap” control system and the
sheep’s safety control system. Such a
simulation would show that control
systems can both control and be
controlled. This kind of simulation
would help dispel what I think is a
common misconception about the control
theory model of organisms –
particularly humans. It is a
misconception that I myself labored
under until just a few years ago. It is
the idea that because organisms are
autonomous control systems – autonomous
in the sense that they set their own
references for the states of their own
perception – they cannot be controlled.
But autonomous control systems can be
controlled, as is demonstrated by the
sheepdogs controlling the sheep. It can
also be easily demonstrated with humans
using the rubber band demo; the E in
this experiment can control the finger
position of the S once S has agreed to
control the position of the knot. And
thanks to Bruce Abbott I demonstrated to
myself that E can still exert this
control even if S continuously – and
autonomously – varies his or her
reference for the position of the knot.> > > > RM: Control theory doesn't say that
organisms (particularly humans) can’t be
controlled; indeed, it shows that they
can be controlled, mainly by disturbance
to a controlled variable. Nor does
control theory show that controlling
organisms (particularly humans) is
necessarily a bad thing to do. What
control theory does show is that
arbitrary control, particularly of
humans by other humans, will almost
certainly lead to conflict. Arbitrary
control is exerting control without
considering the fact that living control
systems are controlling many variables
at the same time and when you
arbitrarily decide to have a person do
something (by disturbing a controlling
variable) what you have them do may
conflict with other things they are
controlling. So to take an example that
Bill used (somewhere), if E decides to
place S’s finger against a hot soldering
iron while controlling Ss finger
position in the rubber band game that
will clearly lconflict with another goal
S has (not getting burned).
Non-arbitrary control is control that is
done with the consent (often implicit
but sometimes explicit) of the would-be
controllee. Non- arbitrary control is, I
think, essential when humans control
other humans. To see why, think about
what happens when people are arbitrarily
controlled (herded) in the same way that
the sheep were. Hint: They don’t like
it. Why do you think not?> > > >Â RM: Anyway, this behavior --
managing flocks – is a very interesting
demonstration of controlling a
perception (of gaps between sheep) via
disturbance of a perception being
controlled by the control systems that
are being controlled.> > > > Best > > > > Rick > > > > > > > > The researchers found that the
behavior could be described by two
simple rules, but more interesting from
a PCT perspective, they found that to
understand the behavior they needed to
view the action from the animal’s
perspectives. According to researcher
Dr. Andrew King:> > "At the beginning we had lots of
different ideas. We started out looking
from a birds eye view, but then we
realised we needed to see what the dog
sees. It sees white, fluffy things. If
there are gaps between them or the gaps
get bigger, the dogs needs to bring them
together."> > > > According to Dr King, sheepdogs are
making the most of the “selfish herd
theory” to bring the animals close
together and move them where they want.> > "One of the things that sheep are
really good at is responding to a threat
by working with their neighbours. It’s
the selfish herd theory: put something
between the threat and you. Individuals
try to minimise the chance of anything
happening to them, so they move towards
the centre of a group."> > The article continues as follows: > > A colleague, Dr Daniel Strombom
from Uppsala University in Sweden, used
the GPS data from the collars to develop
computer simulations. This enabled them
to develop a mathematical shepherding
model.> > The algorithm displays the same
weaving pattern exhibited by sheepdogs.
It helps to solve what has been called
the ‘the shepherding problem’: how one
agent can control a large number of
unwilling agents.> > > > I’d be interested to know whether
the computer algorithm models each
individual’s control systems or operates
by some other method.> > > > Bruce > > > > > >
–
> > Richard S. Marken, Ph.D. > Author of Doing Research on Purpose. > > Now available from Amazon or Barnes
& Noble
> > > > > -- > Richard S. Marken, Ph.D. > Author of Doing Research on Purpose. > Now available from Amazon or Barnes
& Noble
Â
–
Richard S. Marken, Ph.D.
Author of  Doing
Research on Purpose.Â
Now available from Amazon
or Barnes & Noble