Warren Mansell suggested that I post this offline Q & A between Bruce Nevin and myself so here it is. Warren suggested the topic title since that seems to be the main theme of our interaction. This topic of Phenomena Phirst has come up years ago on CSGNet but Warren (and I) think it’s important so here we go again. This comes from an email exchange and I’ve reformatted it slightly for Discourse. ========================================
Hi Bruce
Great questions!
On Sat, Nov 23, 2024 at 6:36 AM Bruce Nevin <bnhpct@gmail.com> wrote:
BN: Hm. Where did Martin say that information is causative?
RM: I don’t know that he ever said that explicitly but it was certainly implied. Martin thought that the disturbance had a detectable effect on the controlled variable that provided the information that allowed a person to act so as to compensate nearly perfectly for the disturbance. So, in the compensatory tracking task, the nearly perfect mirroring of the apparently invisible disturbance occurred, according to Martin, because the effect of the disturbance was visible in the derivative of the movement of the controlled variable. That’s the information that lets the person produce output (move the mouse) in a way that compensates for the effect of the disturbance.
RM: Of course, it doesn’t work that way – the position of the CV is at every instant during a tracking task a simultaneous result of output (O) and disturbance (D). So the derivative of the CV – dCV/dt – is always the derivative of O + D, not just D. The way it works is simply that the closed loop acts to keep the error, r - p = 0 and, as a side effect, O = -D. But Martin was pretty committed to the idea that output was based on (if not caused by) input (information about the disturbance).
BN: Do you have measurements of the perceptual signal represented by the theoretical quantity p to demonstrate an exact equivalence to the environmental measurement (the experimenter’s perception) q.i ?
RM: No, but maybe Henry will soon! The fact is that there has to be a nearly exact equivalence of the actual neural perceptual signal to the aspect of the environment under control – the controlled variable, q.i – or that perceptual signal is not the analog of q.i. For example, in a simple compensatory tracking task, the aspect of the environment that is controlled, CV, is the distance between cursor, C, and target, T; so CV = C - T. In theory this control is achieved via control of a perceptual signal, p, that is an analog of C-T. So I would expect to find an afferent neuron – or neuron bundle? – with a (average?) firing rate that is at least a monotonic function of the CV. Of course, this firing rate will be a bit noisy but the noise should be less than the noisiness of the observed control itself. For example, since we are getting correlations on the order of .99 between actual and model output, O, in a control task, I would expect to find correlations on the order of .99 for the correlation between the C-T and the neural perceptual signal that is thought to correspond to p in the model. This would actually be a possible way to determine whether or not the neural signal being observed does, indeed, correspond to the perceptual signal, p, that is the analog of the CV.
RM: By the way, it’s important to determine the correlation between neural signal and CV when the CV is NOT under control since there is very little variability in the CV when it is under control. So for the tracking task, validating a neural signal as the analog of the CV would involve looking for the correlation between that signal and variations in C - T over a reasonably wide range – like the range of disturbance-produced variation in the CV if it were not under control.
This is from you next email, Bruce:
RM: PCT started with the OBSERVATION of the FACT OF CONTROL AS SEEN IN THE BEHAVIOR OF LIVING THINGS.
BN: This is historically false. Bill learned control theory first, in the Navy and then in subsequent study.
RM: Yes, it’s true that Bill learned control theory before he developed PCT. But it was not Bill’s knowledge of control theory that led him to develop PCT. After all, control theory was being applied in psychology well before Bill developed PCT. Control theory was being applied in human factors psychology since at least 1947 and in cybernetics since at least 1948. But all these applications got it wrong because they based their application of control theory on a behavioral illusion – that inputs cause output. As Powers explains in his 1978 Psych Review paper, earlier applications of control theory failed to see that behavior itself was a control process. Powers’ familiarity with control theory and, especially, with building devices that control, made it possible for him to OBSERVE the fact that BEHAVIOR IS CONTROL. It also didn’t hurt that he was a physicist so he could see that the consistency of behavior was a remarkable achievement.
RM: So it was nice that Bill had learned control theory before developing PCT. But what actually happened is that Bill’s remarkable OBSERVATION of the PHENOMENON OF CONTROL as seen in the BEHAVIOR of living things led to the correct application of a theory with which he was already familiar as an explanation of that phenomenon. Phenomena phirst!
RM: By the way, I’m watching a nice PBS documentary on Leonardo da Vinci. It turns out he was a big “phenomena first” guy, just like my other scientific heroes: Galileo, Faraday, & Powers.