Hi Kent, it’s actually rare to read you do any kind of rant and I don’t regard your eloquent defence of CEVs as a rant at all!
Warren
···
On 10 Dec 2016, at 00:11, McClelland, Kent MCCLEL@Grinnell.EDU wrote:
from Kent McClelland (2016.12.09.1400)
Erling Jorgensen (2016.12.08 1150 EST)
Rick Marken (2016.12.07.1710)
Rick and Rupert have argued in this thread that perceptions constructed from clusters of sensory input variables do not necessarily have any counterparts in the physical environment. Therefore, they argue, in Martin Taylor’s “mirror world� diagram (2016.10.16.10.32),
where dots above the dividing line between organism and environment represent perceptions and dots below the line represent complex environmental variables (CEVs), the dots above the line are real, while those below the line aren’t. Thus, Rick concludes, “there’s
no such thing as a CEVâ€? (2016.10.27.1300). Rick’s most recent post in the thread offers a selection of quotes from Bill Powers in which Bill makes similar arguments.While I appreciate the logic of this argument, which takes as its frame of reference the relationship between the individual actor/perceiver and the individual’s environment, I still think that it’s short-sighted, because it misses the bigger picture that could
be revealed by adopting a sociological frame of reference, which would pay attention the fact that the individual’s environment contains other people.Bill Powers provided the classic statement of Rick and Rupert’s argument in his lemonade example in Behavior: The Control of Perception. Here’s what he said on p. 112 of the 2005 edition:
This is a good opportunity to emphasize a “philosophical fact” that emerges from this theory: perceptual signals depend on physical events, but what they represent does not necessarily
have any physical significance…. The taste of fresh lemonade, for example, contains an easily recognizable vector, derived from the intensity signals generated by sugar and acid (together with some oil smells). However unitary and real this vector seems, there
is no physical entity corresponding to it….This means we would be much safer in general to speak of sensation-creating input functions rather than sensation-recognizing functions. To speak of recognition implies tacitly that the environment contains an entity to be recognized, and that all we have to
do is learn to detect it. It seems far more realistic to me to speak instead of functions that construct perceptions with the question of external counterparts to these perceptions being treated with much skepticism.Bill’s radical skepticism here is fine as far as it goes. Yes, there’s nothing in the environment corresponding to the taste of lemonade. Lemonade is a mixture, not a chemical compound. But how is it that he can talk about the taste of lemonade and be confident
that his readers will know what he’s talking about? It’s because there IS something in their environment, and quite a lot of that something, that has the precise combination of chemical ingredients to allow almost anyone who samples it to experience the perception
of tasting lemonade.
It’s called “lemonade," and it’s a liquid so ubiquitous in the Western world that most people are exposed to it repeatedly over their lives and thus develop by reorganization a dedicated control system somewhere in their perceptual hierarchy for
“recognizing� lemonade when they drink it and saying unequivocally whether any liquid they drink happens to taste like lemonade or not.
So it seems ridiculous to me to say that there’s nothing in the environment of the individual that can compute from that vector of physical variables the perception of the taste of lemonade (or whatever perception you want to talk about that is
based on widespread cultural patterns), when there are millions upon millions of people in the individual’s environment who can do just that. And these millions of people by their collective efforts to control their perceptions of the taste of lemonade end
up creating and drinking billions of gallons of the stuff. The liquid is available in bottled form in every supermarket or convenience store.
Our collective control of the perception of a liquid called lemonade is a “stabilized niche� in the feedback function, as Erling puts it in his latest post, for any individual who may be trying to decide what to drink with lunch. Or you could
call it a collectively controlled “invariance,� one that “can form the basis for a new perceptual category,� as Bill says in his chapter describing reorganization (BCP 2005, p. 204), confronting any child who grows up in the social environment of the Western
world.
[By the way, Rick has asked me repeatedly for an example of something that is collectively controlled with conflict but yet has longterm stability. I offer the perception of the “taste for lemonade.� Everybody knows what lemonade contains: sugar,
water, and lemon juice. But people have very different reference values for what the drink should taste like. Compare the taste of the potent Italian “limonade� to the sickly sweet and watered down drink often served in the USA, or to the vile chemical concoction
that goes by the name of Country Time Lemonade.]
My feeling is that it’s important for us to be able to talk from the PCT perspective about these “stabilized niches in the feedback function� that serve, as Erling notes, as a kind stable platform for effective control of other perceptions. Coining
the term “atenfel� was one attempt to disaggregate feedback functions and pick out those regions of dependably stable, socially produced invariance that facilitate effective control, so that they can become a focus of PCT-informed investigation. The idea
of CEVs is another way to conceptualize the environmental stabilities that are collectively produced.
I had been wondering why Rick has been so hostile to the notion of a CEV, while to me it makes intuitive sense, and it occurred to me that this disagreement may also be a matter of his individual frame of reference vs. my social frame of reference.
If we’re considering a model of how an individual perceives some unknown thing in the environment, there’s no need to postulate a CEV. The model works fine without it. But as soon as we add a second person to the model who is also controlling the same perception
in the same physical environment, that is, we make it into an interactive model of collective control rather than individual behavior, the CEV becomes necessary. The feedback functions of the two actors must converge in some set of environmental variables
for any interaction to take place.
Consider Tom Bourbon’s experiment in collective control, which Rick holds up as an ideal example of PCT-infomed sociology (Bourbon, W. Thomas, Invitation to the dance: Explaining the variance when control systems interact.
American Behavioral Scientist. September/October 1990, vol. 34 no. 1, 95-105. doi: 10.1177/0002764290034001009).
The task in this experiment was to use two joysticks to keep two cursors on a computer screen in line with each other and with a target. A subject could use one joystick for one cursor and one for the other, but the movements of one joystick also
disturbed the other cursor, and vice versa. Bourbon showed that this task could be equally well done by a single person with a joystick in each hand or by two people each running a single joystick. (From my point of view, the two-person experiment is an example
of cooperative collective control, because both subjects control their perceptions of the cursor positions using the same reference values for alignment.)
Here is the diagram that Tom provided to show the PCT model of the two-person experiment.
Notice that the two PCT models for the two experimental subjects (one on the right and the other on the left) meet in the center of the diagram in a set of environmental variables—the CEV for this modeel. For the experiment to work, the two subjects
have to be looking at the same computer screen. In other words, their feedback functions have to pass through the same “stabilized niche� of computer, screen, and moving cursors. Without that region of invariance in their common environment, the two people
in the experiment would not be interacting at all.
If we want PCT to be perceived as relevant to social sciences like political science, economics, sociology, and anthropology, and to the humanities as well, we need to develop a clear analytic vocabulary for talking about the collectively controlled
stabilities in our common social environments, not just what is going on in people’s heads. Maybe CEV, atenfel, and mirror world aren’t the right words for it, but we need something. To just conceptualize the environment as a pulsating set of unconnected physical
variables or else a mush of undifferentiated individual feedback functions, pretending that every individual constructs from that morass his own independent set of perceptions, will not do.
And even to do the Test for the Controlled Variable with an individual, we need to be able to take seriously the stabilized environments in which social interaction occurs. If it weren’t for the social and cultural stabilities that we’re all exposed
to growing up—the “boss realitiesâ€? that disciplinee our reorganizing sets of perceptual control systems into hierarchies that resemble one another’s—we would never be able to identify tthe perceptions another person is apparently controlling or or talk about
them in a meaningful way. These social realities are built into our individual psychology. We’ve got to pay some serious attention to them.
Enough of my rant for now!
Best to all,
Kent
On Dec 8, 2016, at 12:01 PM, Erling Jorgensen EJorgensen@riverbendcmhc.org wrote:
[From Erling Jorgensen (2016.12.08 1150 EST)]
Rick Marken (2016.12.07.1710)
[RM] (referring to your modification of Martin’s diagram, not reproduced here…) One function that defines the variable q.i is the perceptual function inside the system controlling q.i. Another could be in an observer (the silhouette to the left of q.i)
capable of computing a function of the environmental variables, v’s, that is the same as the perceptual function of the control system.[EJ] Rick, I appreciate the archival search you did to find some of Bill Powers’ thoughts on this issue. For one thing, it helps me relax about designating the CV term (Controlled Variable) the Observer’s version of the perception seemingly being controlled.
As Bill states:Bill Powers (961224.1145 MST)
BP: Remember that as far as the observer is concerned, what is controlled is ONLY the CV. The idea that this CV is represented by a perceptual signal inside the other system is theoretical. We can observe CV, but not p. When we apply a disturbance, we apply
it to CV, not to p. The action that opposes the effect of the disturbance acts on CV, not p. The Test does not involve p at all. It involves only observables[EJ] This says that from the Observer’s point of view, the only thing they have to work with is the CV. In the Test for the Controlled Variable, they build up a hypothesis about the other person’s relation to the CV – attempting to control it or not – based
on what happens following the Observer’s disturbance of that variable. If the CV moves as expected, then try something else, because that’s not the variable the other is controlling for. But if the CV does not move as much as expected from their own disturbance,
that is a significant finding, seemingly because something or someone is keeping that result from happening. When variables are stabilized in that way, we suspect “control”, with a very useful theoretical model for what might be going on. And indeed, you
and Bill developed the notion of a “Stability Factor”, to quantify the degree of that hypothesized control.[EJ] However, I disagree with an earlier point you (and Bill) make. The relevant context is the two sentences prior to Bill’s quote above:
Bruce Abbott (961224.1310 EST)
BA: Rick’s response was to deny that the distinction Martin was making between “stabilized” and “controlled” was useful. CV, he said, either is controlled or is not controlled.
BP: I would tend to agree with Rick, because of my definition of control given above.
[EJ] I have two reasons for considering the notion of “stabilized-but-not-controlled” to be useful. The first reason derives from Kent McClelland’s modeling of conflictive control situations. When two living control systems are trying to keep the same perceptual
variable in two different reference states, the result is often a “virtual reference level” somewhere in between the two preferred states, roughly proportional to the relative contributions of each party’s output gain. While neither party achieves satisfactory
“control” of the variable, its value is definitely “stabilized” somewhere in the middle, with each party pulling as hard as they can. In fact, this is how Bill Powers used to talk about such situations – when the output of each party is maxed out in this
way, they have lost effective control, and the variable may well drift according to whatever other disturbances are in play.[EJ] My other reason for considering “stabilized” a useful concept that does not simply overlap with “control” was given in my recent post (Erling Jorgensen (2016.12.01 1430 EST). There I argued that a stabilized niche can be an important part of the Environmental
Feedback Function for controlling other variables. Here, the term stability refers to properties of a given control loop, not the values generated by the loop itself. As I said in more detail there, “Stabilized properties, for more effective control.”All the best,
Erling
<PastedGraphic-4.tiff>